Curriculum Plan Critique Assignment Instructions Overview The purpose of this assignment is for you to critique a curriculum plan based upon what you have learned in this course by describing the stre

The Tyler Rationale Author(s): Herbert M. Kliebard Source: The School Review , Feb., 1970 , Vol. 78, No. 2 (Feb., 1970), pp. 259-272 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1084240 REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1084240?seq=1&cid=pdf- reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal The Tyler Rationale Herbert M. Kliebard, University of Wisconsin One of the disturbing characteristics of the curriculum field is its lack of historical perspective. New breakthroughs are solemnly proclaimed when in fact they represent minor modifications of early proposals, and, conversely, anachronistic dogmas and doctrines maintain a cur- rency and uncritical acceptance far beyond their present merit. The most persistent theoretical formulation in the field of curriculum has been Ralph Tyler's syllabus for Education 360 at the University of Chicago, Basic Principles of Curriculum and Instruction, or, as it is widely known, the Tyler rationale.' Tyler's claims for his rationale are modest, but, over time, his proposal for rationally developing a curriculum has been raised almost to the status of revealed doctrine. In the recent issue of the Review of Educational Research devoted to curriculum, Goodlad, commenting on the state of the field, reports that "as far as the major questions to be answered in developing a curriculum are concerned, most of the authors in [the] 1960 and 1969 [curriculum issues of the Review] assume those set forth in 1950 by Ralph Tyler." Later, he concludes with obvious disappointment, "General theory and conceptualization in curriculum appear to have advanced very little during the last decade."2 Perhaps the twentieth anniversary of the publication of the Tyler rationale is an appropri- ate time to reexamine and reevaluate some of its central features. Tyler's rationale revolves around four central questions which Tyler feels need answers if the process of curriculum development is to proceed: 1. What educational purposes should the school seek to attain? February 1970 259 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal 2. What educational experiences can be provided that are likely to attain these purposes? 3. How can these educational experiences be effectively organized? 4: How can we determine whether these purposes are being at- tained?3 These questions may be reformulated into the familiar four-step process by which a curriculum is developed: stating objectives, se- lecting "experiences," organizing "experiences," and evaluating.4 The Tyler rationale is essentially an elaboration and explication of these steps. The most crucial step in this doctrine is obviously the first since all the others proceed from and wait upon the statement of objectives. As Tyler puts it, "If we are to study an educational pro- gram systematically and intelligently we must first be sure as to the educational objectives aimed at."5 The Selection of Educational Objectives Tyler's section on educational objectives is a description of the three sources of objectives: studies of learners, studies of contempo- rary life, and suggestions from subject-matter specialists, as well as an account of how data derived from these "sources" are to be "fil- tered" through philosophical and psychological "screens." The three sources of educational objectives encapsulate several traditional doc- trines in the curriculum field over which much ideological blood had been spilled in the previous several decades. The doctrines proceeded from different theoretical assumptions, and each of them had its own spokesmen, its own adherents, and its own rhetoric. Tyler's proposal accepts them all, which probably accounts in part for its wide popu- larity. While we are aware that compromise is the recourse frequently taken in the fields of diplomatic or labor negotiation, simple eclecti- cism may not be the most efficacious way to proceed in theorizing. When Dewey, for example, identified the fundamental factors in the educative process as the child and the "values incarnate in the ma- tured experience of the adult," the psychological and the logical, his solution was not to accept them both but "to discover a reality to which each belongs."6 In other words, when faced with essentially the same problem of warring educational doctrines, Dewey's ap- proach is to creatively reformulate the problem; Tyler's is to lay them all out side by side. 260 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal Subject Matter as a Source of Objectives Of the three "sources"-studies of the learners themselves, studies of contemporary life, and suggestions about objectives from subject- matter specialists-the last one seems curiously distorted and out of place. Perhaps this is because Tyler begins the section by profoundly misconceiving the role and function of the Committee of Ten. He attributes to the Committee of Ten a set of objectives which, he claims, has subsequently been followed by thousands of secondary schools. In point of fact, the notion of objectives in the sense that Tyler defines the term was not used and probably had not even oc- curred to the members of the Committee of Ten. What they proposed were not objectives, but "four programmes": Classical, Latin-Scien- tific, Modern Languages, and English. Under each of these rubrics is a listing of the subjects that constitute each of the four courses of study. This recommendation is followed by the reports of the various individual committees on what content should be included and what methods should be used in the various subject fields. Unless Tyler is using the term "objective" as being synonymous with "content" (in which case it would lose all its importance as a conceptyf W K H Q W K e use of the term "objectives" in the context of the report of the Com- mittee of Ten is erroneous. Probably the only sense in which the term "objective" is applicable to the Committee of Ten report is in connection with the broad objective of mental training to which it subscribes. An even more serious error follows: "It seems clear that the Com- mittee of Ten thought it was answering the question: What should be the elementary instruction for students who are later to carry on much more advanced work in the field. Hence, the report in His- tory, for example, seems to present objectives [sic] for the beginning courses for persons who are training to be historians. Similarly the report in Mathematics outlines objectives [sic] for the beginning courses in the training of a mathematician."7 As a matter of fact, one of the central questions that the Committee of Ten considered was, "Should the subject be treated differently for pupils who are going to college, for those who are going to a scien- tific school, and for those, who, presumably, are going to neither?"8 The Committee decided unanimously in the negative. The subcom- mittee on history, civil government, and political economy, for ex- ample, reported that it was "unanimously against making such a February 1970 261 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal distinction"9 and passed a resolution that "instruction in history and related subjects ought to be precisely the same for pupils on their way to college or the scientific school, as for those who expect to stop at the end of grammar school, or at the end of the high school."' Evidently, the Committee of Ten was acutely aware of the question of a differentiated curriculum based on probable destination. It sim- ply rejected the doctrine that makes a prediction about one's future status or occupation a valid basis for the curriculum in general edu- cation. The objective of mental training, apparently, was conceived to be of such importance as to apply to all, regardless of destination. Tyler's interpretation of the Committee of Ten report is more than a trivial historical misconception. It illustrates one of his fun- damental presuppositions about the subjects in the curriculum. Tyler conceives of subjects as performing certain "functions." These func- tions may take the form of a kind of definition of the field of study itself such as when he sees a function of science to be enabling the student to obtain a "clearer understanding of the world as it is viewed by the scientist and man's relation to it, and the place of the world in the larger universe"; or the subject may perform external func- tions such as the contribution of science to the improvement of indi- vidual or public health or to the conservation of natural resources. The first sense of function is essentially a way of characterizing a field of study; in the second sense of function, the subject field serves as an instrument for achieving objectives drawn from Tyler's other two sources. Tyler's apparent predisposition to the latter sense of function seems to be at the heart of his misreading of the Committee of Ten report. To Tyler, studying history or algebra (as was uni- versally recommended by the Committee of Tenyf L I W K H \ D U H Q R t meeting an obvious individual or social need, is a way of fulfilling the vocational needs of a budding historian or mathematician. Other- wise, how can one justify the existence of mathematics qua mathe- matics in the curriculum? As such, "suggestions from subject-matter specialists" is really not a source in the sense that the other two are. Subject matter is mainly one of several means by which one fulfills individual needs such as vocational aspirations or meets social ex- pectations. Needs of the Learner as a Source of Objectives The section on the "learners themselves as a source of educational objectives," although it is less strained and more analytical than the 262 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal one on subject matter, is nevertheless elliptical. Tyler proceeds from the assumption that "education is a process of changing behavior patterns of people.""1 This notion, of course, is now widely popular in this country, but, even if one were to accept such a view, it would be important to know the ways in which education would be differ- ent from other means of changing behavior, such as, hypnosis, shock treatment, brainwashing, sensitivity training, indoctrination, drug therapy, and torture. Given such a definition, the differences be- tween education and these other ways of changing behavior are not obvious or simple. Tyler proceeds from his basic definition of education to a con- sideration of the reason for wanting to study the learner: "A study of the learners themselves would seek to identify needed changes in behavior patterns of the students which the educational institution should seek to produce."'12 There follows an extended discussion of "needs," how they are determined, and how they contribute to the determination of educational objectives. The notion of needs as a basis for curriculum development was not a new one when Tyler used it in 1950. It had been a stable element in the curriculum liter- ature for about three decades.13 When tied to the biological concept of homeostasis, the term "needs" seems to have a clear-cut meaning. Hunger, for example, may be conveniently translated into a need for food when one has in mind a physiological state of equilibrium. Need becomes a much trickier concept when one speaks of the "need of a haircut" or the "need for a good spanking." These needs involve rather complex social norms on which good men and true may differ sharply. Tyler astutely recognized that the concept of need has no meaning without a set of norms, and he described the kind of study he envisioned essentially as a two-step process: "first, finding the present status of the students, and second, comparing this status to acceptable norms in order to identify the gaps or needs."14 This formulation is virtually identical to what Bobbitt referred to as "shortcomings" in the first book written exclusively on the curricu- lum, published in 1918.15 The key term, in Tyler's version, of course, is "acceptable norms." They are neither self-evident nor easy to for- mulate. One of Tyler's illustrations of the process he advocates is a case in point: A "discovery" is made that 60 percent of ninth-grade boys read only comic strips. The "unimaginative" teacher, Tyler says, might interpret this as suggesting the need for more attention to comic February 1970 263 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal strips in the classroom; the imaginative teacher uses the data as a justification "for setting up objectives gradually to broaden and deepen these reading interests."'6 What is the acceptable norm im- plicit in Tyler's illustration? Apparently, it is not a statistical norm since this could imply that the 40 percent minority of boys should be encouraged to emulate the 60 percent majority. The norm seems to be the simple conviction that having broader and deeper reading interests is better than limiting oneself to the reading of comic strips. The question is what does the 60 percent figure contribute to the process of stating educational objectives. What difference would it have made if the figure were 80 percent or 40 percent? The key fac- tor seems to be the nature and strength of the teacher's conviction as the acceptable norm, toward which the status study contributes very little. The whole notion of need has no meaning without an established norm, and, therefore, it is impossible even to identify "needs" with- out it. As Archambault put it, "An objective need can be discovered, but only within a completely defined context in which the normal level of attainment can be clarified.""7 Furthermore, even when a genuine need is identified, the role of the school as an institution for the remediation of that or other needs would have to be consid- ered. Even the course that remediation should take once the need and the responsibility have been established is an open question. These serious value questions associated with the identification and remediation of needs make the concept a deceptively complex one whose advantages are more apparent than real. Komisar, for example, has described this double use of need, "one to report deficiencies and another to prescribe for their alleviation," as so vague and elusive as to constitute a "linguistic luxury."'" As already mentioned, Tyler is acutely aware of the difficulties of "deriving" educational objectives from studies of the child. His last word on the subject in this section is to suggest to his students that they compile some data and then try using those data as the basis for formulating objectives. He suggests this exercise in part to illustrate the difficulty of the process. Given the almost impossible complexity of the procedure and the crucial but perhaps arbitrary role of the interpreter's value structure or "philosophy of life and of education," one wonders whether the concept of need deserves any place in the process of formulating objectives. Certainly, the concept of need turns out to be of no help in so far as avoiding central value decisions as 264 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal the basis for the selection of educational objectives, and without that feature much of its appeal seems to disappear. As Dearden concluded in his analysis of the term: "The concept of 'need' is an attractive one in education because it seems to offer an escape from arguments about value by means of a straightforward appeal to the facts empiri- cally determined by the expert. But . . . it is false to suppose that judgments of value can thus be escaped. Such judgments may be as- sumed without any awareness that assumptions are being made, but they are not escaped."19 Studies of Contemporary Life as a Source of Objectives Tyler's section on studies of contemporary life as a source of cur- ricular objectives follows the pattern set by the section on the learner. His conception of the role that such studies play in determining objectives is also similar in many respects to that of his spiritual ancestor, Franklin Bobbitt, who stimulated the practice of activity analysis in the curriculum field. Like Bobbitt, Tyler urges that one "divide life" into a set of manageable categories and then proceed to collect data of various kinds which may be fitted into these cate- gories. One of Tyler's illustrations is especially reminiscent of Bob- bitt: "Students in the school obtain[ed] from their parents for several days the problems they were having to solve that involved arithmetic. The collection and analysis of this set of problems suggested the arithmetic operations and the kinds of mathematical problems which are commonly encountered by adults, and became the basis of the arithmetic curriculum."20 Tyler tends to be more explicitly aware than Bobbitt of the tra- ditional criticisms that have been directed against this approach. Bode, for example, once pointed out that "no scientific analysis known to man can determine the desirability or the need of any- thing." The question of whether a community with a given burglary rate needs a larger police force or more burglars is entirely a question of what the community wants.21 Tyler's implicit response to this and other traditional criticism of this approach is to argue that in his rationale studies of contemporary life do not constitute the sole basis for deriving objectives, and, of course, that such studies have to be checked against "an acceptable educational philosophy."22 In this sense, the contemporary life source is just as dependent on the philo- sophical screen as is the learner source. February 1970 265 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal The Philosophical Screen Tyler's treatment of the section on the learner and on contempo- rary life as sources of educational objectives are roughly parallel. In each case, Tyler is aware of the serious shortcomings of the source but assumes that they can be overcome, first, by not relying exclu- sively on any one of them-in a sense counting on his eclecticism to blunt the criticism. And second (and probably more importantyf K e appeals to philosophy as the means for covering any deficiencies. This suggests that it is philosophy after all that is the source of Tyler's objectives and that the stipulated three sources are mere window dressing. It is Tyler's use of the concept of a philosophical screen, then, that is most crucial in understanding his rationale, at least in so far as stating the objectives is concerned. Even if we were to grant that people go through life with some kind of primitive value structure spinning around in their heads, to say that educational objectives somehow flow out of such a value structure is to say practically nothing at all. Tyler's proposal that educational objectives be filtered through a philosophical screen is not so much demonstrably false as it is trivial, almost vacuous. It simply does not address itself in any significant sense to the question of which objectives we leave in and which we throw out once we have committed ourselves to the task of stating them. Filtering educational objectives through a philosophical screen is simply another way of saying that one is forced to make choices from among the thousands or perhaps millions of objectives that one can draw from the sources that Tyler cites. (The number of objectives is a function of the level of specificity.yf % R E E L W W Z D V I D F H G Z L W K W K H V D P H S U H G L F D P H Q W Z K H Q K e was engaged in his massive curriculum project in Los Angeles in 1921-23. Bobbitt's solution was to seek "the common judgment of thoughtful men and women,''23 an appeal to consensus. Tyler's ap- peal is to divine philosophy, but the effect is equally arbitrary as long as we are still in the dark as to how one arrives at a philosophy and how one engages in the screening process. Take, for example, one of Tyler's own illustrations of how a phi- losophy operates: "If the school believes that its primary function is to teach people to adjust to society it will strongly emphasize obedi- ence to present authorities, loyalty to the present forms and tradi- tions, skills in carrying on the present techniques of life; whereas if it emphasizes the revolutionary function of the school it will be more 266 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal concerned with critical analysis, ability to meet new problems, in- dependence and self-direction, freedom, and self-discipline. Again, it is clear that the nature of the philosophy of the school can affect the selection of educational objectives."24 Although Tyler appears else- where to have a personal predilection for the latter philosophy, we really have no criterion to appeal to in making a choice. We are urged only to make our educational objectives consistent with our educational philosophy, and this makes the choice of objectives pre- cisely as arbitrary as the choice of philosophy. One may, therefore, express a philosophy that conceives of human beings as instruments of the state and the function of the schools as programming the youth of the nation to react in a fixed manner when appropriate stimuli are presented. As long as we derive a set of objectives consistent with this philosophy (and perhaps make a brief pass at the three sourcesyf , we have developed our objectives in line with the Tyler rationale. The point is that, given the notion of educational objectives and the necessity of stating them explicitly and consistently with a philos- ophy, it makes all the difference in the world what one's guiding phi- losophy is since that consistency can be as much a sin as a virtue. The rationale offers little by way of a guide for curriculum making be- cause it excludes so little. Popper's dictum holds not only for science, but all intellectual endeavor: "Science does not aim, primarily, at high probabilities. It aims at high informative content, well backed by experience. But a hypothesis may be very probable simply because it tells us nothing or very little. A high degree of probability is there- fore not an indication of 'goodness'-it may be merely a symptom of low informative content."25 Tyler's central hypothesis that a state- ment of objectives derives in some manner from a philosophy, while highly probable, tells us very little indeed. Selection and Organization of Learning Experiences Once the crucial first step of stating objectives is accomplished, the rationale proceeds relentlessly through the steps of the selection and organization of learning experiences as the means for achieving the ends and, finally, evaluating in terms of those ends. Typically, Tyler recognizes a crucial problem in connection with the concept of a learning experience but passes quickly over it: The problem is how can learning experiences be selected by a teacher or a curriculum maker when they are defined as the interaction between a student and February 1970 267 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal his environment. By definition, then, the learning experience is in some part a function of the perceptions, interests, and previous ex- perience of the student. At least this part of the learning experience is not within the power of the teacher to select. While Tyler is ex- plicitly aware of this, he nevertheless maintains that the teacher can control the learning experience through the "manipulation of the environment in such a way as to set up stimulating situations-situ- ations that will evoke the kind of behavior desired."26 The Pavlovian overtones of such a solution are not discussed. Evaluation "The process of evaluation," according to Tyler, "is essentially the process of determining to what extent the educational objectives are actually being realized by the program of curriculum and instruc- tion."27 In other words, the statement of objectives not only serves as the basis for the selection and organization of learning experiences, but the standard against which the program is assessed. To Tyler, then, evaluation is a process by which one matches initial expecta- tions in the form of behavioral objectives with outcomes. Such a con- ception has a certain commonsensical appeal, and, especially when fortified with models from industry and systems analysis, it seems like a supremely wise and practical way to appraise the success of a venture. Actually, curriculum evaluation as a kind of product con- trol was set forth by Bobbitt as early as 1922,28 but product control when applied to curriculum presents certain difficulties. One of the difficulties lies in the nature of an aim or objective and whether it serves as the terminus for activity in the sense that the Tyler rationale implies. In other words, is an objective an end point or a turning point? Dewey argued for the latter: "Ends arise and function within action. They are not, as current theories too often imply, things lying outside activity at which the latter is directed. They are not ends or termini of action at all. They are terminals of deliberation, and so turning points in activity."29 If ends arise only within activity it is not clear how one can state objectives before the activity (learning experienceyf E H J L Q V ' H Z H \ V S R V L W L R Q W K H Q K D V L P - portant consequences not just for Tyler's process of evaluation but for the rationale as a whole. It would mean, for example, that the starting point for a model of curriculum and instruction is not the 268 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal statement of objectives but the activity (learning experienceyf D Q d whatever objectives do appear will arise within that activity as a way of adding a new dimension to it. Under these circumstances, the process of evaluation would not be seen as one of matching antici- pated consequences with actual outcomes, but as one of describing and of applying criteria of excellence to the activity itself. This view would recognize Dewey's claim that "even the most important among all the consequences of an act is not necessarily its aim,"80 and it would be consistent with Merton's important distinction between manifest and latent functions.31 The importance of description as a key element in the process of evaluation has also been emphasized by Cronbach: "When evalua- tion is carried out in the service of course improvement, the chief aim is to ascertain what effects the course has .... This is not to inquire merely whether the course is effective or ineffective. Outcomes of instruction are multidimensional, and a satisfactory investigation will map out the effects of the course along these dimensions sepa- rately."32 The most significant dimensions of an educational activity or any activity may be those that are completely unplanned and wholly unanticipated. An evaluation procedure that ignores this fact is plainly unsatisfactory. Summary and Conclusion The crucial first step in the Tyler rationale on which all else hinges is the statement of objectives. The objectives are to be drawn from three sources: studies of the learner, studies of society, and sug- gestions from subject-matter specialists. Data drawn from these sources are to be filtered through philosophical and psychological screens. Upon examination, the last of the three sources turns out to be no source at all but a means of achieving objectives drawn from the other two. Studies of the learner and of society depend so heavily for their standing as sources on the philosophical screen that it is actually the philosophical screen that determines the nature and scope of the objectives. To say that educational objectives are drawn from one's philosophy, in turn, is only to say that one must make choices about educational objectives in some way related to one's value structure. This is to say so little about the process of selecting objectives as to be virtually meaningless. One wonders whether the long-standing insistence by curriculum theorists that the first step February 1970 269 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal in making a curriculum be the specification of objectives has any merit whatsoever. It is even questionable whether stating objectives at all, when they represent external goals allegedly reached through the manipulation of learning experiences, is a fruitful way to con- ceive of the process of curriculum planning. Certainly, the whole concept of a learning experience requires much more analysis than it has been given. Finally, the simplistic notion that evaluation is a process of matching objectives with outcomes leaves much to be desired. It ignores what may be the more significant latent outcomes in favor of the manifest and anticipated ones, and it minimizes the vital relationship between ends and means. One reason for the success of the Tyler rationale is its very ration- ality. It is an eminently reasonable framework for developing a cur- riculum; it duly compromises between warring extremes and skirts the pitfalls to which the doctrinaire are subject. In one sense, the Tyler rationale is imperishable. In some form, it will always stand as the model of curriculum development for those who conceive of the curriculum as a complex machinery for transforming the crude raw material that children bring with them to school into a finished and useful product. By definition, the production model of curriculum and instruction begins with a blueprint for how the student will turn out once we get through with him. Tyler's version of the model avoids the patent absurdity of, let us say, Mager's by drawing that blueprint in broad outline rather than in minute detail.33 For his moderation and his wisdom as well as his impact, Ralph Tyler deserves to be enshrined in whatever hall of fame the field of curriculum may wish to establish. But the field of curriculum, in its turn, must recognize the Tyler rationale for what it is: Ralph Tyler's version of how a curriculum should be developed-not the universal model of curriculum development. Goodlad once claimed that "Tyler put the capstone on one epoch of curriculum inquiry."84 The new epoch is long overdue. 270 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal NOTES 1. Ralph W. Tyler, Basic Principles of Curriculum and Instruction (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1950yf 1 R W H G L I I H U H Q F H V L Q S D J L Q D W L R Q L Q S U L Q W L Q J . 2. John I. Goodlad, "Curriculum: State of the Field," Review of Educational Research 39 (1969yf . 3. Tyler, pp. 1-2. 4. I have argued elsewhere that the characteristic mode of thought associated with the field of curriculum frequently manifests itself in enumeration and par- ticularization as a response to highly complex questions. Herbert M. Kliebard, "The Curriculum Field in Retrospect," in Technology and the Curriculum, ed. Paul W. F. Witt (New York: Teachers College Press, 1968yf S S . 5. Tyler, p. 3. 6. John Dewey, "The Child and the Curriculum," in John Dewey on Educa- tion, ed. Reginald D. Archambault (New York: Random House, 1964yf S S - 40. (Originally published by University of Chicago Press in 1902.yf 7. Tyler, p. 17. 8. National Education Association, Report of the Committee on Secondary School Studies (Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 1893yf S . 9. Ibid, p. 203. 10. Ibid, p. 165. 11. Tyler, p. 4. 12. Ibid, pp. 4-5. 13. See, e.g., H. H. Giles, S. P. McCutchen, and A. N. Zechiel, Exploring the Curriculum (New York: Harper &c Bros., 1942yf 9 7 7 K D \ H U & D U R O L Q H % = D F K U \ , and Ruth Kotinsky, Reorganizing Secondary Education (New York: Appleton Century, 1939yf 7 K H I R U P H U Z R U N Z D V R Q H R I W K H Y R O X P H V W R F R P H R X W R I W K H 3 U R - gressive Education Association's Eight-Year Study. Tyler was closely associated with that research. The latter volume was published under the auspices of the Progressive Education Association's Commission on Secondary School Curriculum. Tyler was also a member of the committee that prepared the NSSE yearbook on needs. Nelson B. Henry, ed., Adapting the Secondary School Program to the Needs of Youth, Fifty-second Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Educa- tion, pt. 1 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953yf $ Q H D U O \ V W D W H P H Q W R f needs in relation to curriculum organization appeared in The Development of the High-School Curriculum, Sixth Yearbook of the Department of Superinten- dence (Washington, D.C.: Department of Superintendence, 1928yf 1 H H G V D V W K e basis for the curriculum in English was mentioned by E. L. Miller as early as 1922. North Central Association of Colleges and Secondary Schools, Proceedings of the Twenty-seventh Annual Meeting of the North Central Association of Colleges and Secondary Schools (Cedar Rapids, Iowa: Torch Press, 1922yf S . 14. Tyler, p. 6. 15. Franklin Bobbitt, The Curriculum (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1918yf , p. 45 ff. 16. Tyler, p. 10. 17. Reginald D. Archambault, "The Concept of Need and Its Relation to Cer- tain Aspects of Educational Theory," Harvard Educational Review 27 (1957yf . 18. B. Paul Komisar, "'Need' and the Needs Curriculum," in Language and Concepts in Education, eds. B. O. Smith and Robert H. Ennis (Chicago: Rand McNally &8 Co., 1961yf S . 19. R. F. Dearden, " 'Needs' in Education," British Journal of Educational Studies 14 (1966yf . February 1970 271 This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Reappraisal 20. Tyler, pp. 16-17. 21. Boyd H. Bode, Modern Educational Theories (New York: Macmillan Co., 1927yf S S . 22. Tyler, p. 13. 23. Franklin Bobbitt, Curriculum-making in Los Angeles, Supplementary Edu- cational Monographs no. 20 (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1922yf S . 24. Tyler, p. 23. 25. Karl Popper, "Degree of Confirmation," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 6 (1955yf R U L J L Q D O L W D O L F V \f. 26. Tyler, p. 42. 27. Ibid., p. 69. 28. Franklin Bobbitt, "The Objectives of Secondary Education," School Re- view 28 (1920yf . 29. John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (New York: Random House, 1922yf S 2 U L J L Q D O O \ S X E O L V K H G E \ + H Q U \ + R O W & R \f 30. Ibid., p. 227. 31. Robert K. Merton, "Manifest and Latent Functions," in Social Theory and Social Structure (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1957yf S S . 32. Lee J. Cronbach, "Evaluation for Course Improvement," New Curricula, ed. Robert W. Heath (New York: Harper & Row, 1964yf S R U L J L Q D O L W D O L F V \f. 33. Robert F. Mager, Preparing Instructional Objectives (Palo Alto, Calif.: Fearon Publishers, 1962yf . 34. John I. Goodlad, "The Development of a Conceptual System for Dealing with Problems of Curriculum and Instruction," U.S. Department of Health, Edu- cation, and Welfare, Office of Education Cooperative Research Project no. 454 (Los Angeles: Institute for the Development of Educational Activities, UCLA, 1966yf S . 272 School Review This content downloaded from 208.95.48.49 on Wed, 10 Nov 2021 23:44:01 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms