one guide is attached with 3 readings. Tutor needs to choose only 1. Critical Response Papers: Tutor is required to write 3 Critical Response Papers throughout the term. Each paper should be about 1

Performative Acts and Gender

Constitution: An Essay in Phenomenology

and Feminist Theory

Judith Butler

Philosophers rarely think about acting in the theatrical sense, but they do have a

discourse of 'acts' that maintains associative semantic meanings with theories of

performance and acting. For example, John Searle's 'speech acts,' those verbal as-

surances and promises which seem not only to refer to a speaking relationship, but

to constitute a moral bond between speakers, illustrate one of the illocutionary ges- tures that constitutes the stage of the analytic philosophy of language. Further, 'action

theory,' a domain of moral philosophy, seeks to understand what it is 'to do' prior to any claim of what one ought to do. Finally, the phenomenological theory of 'acts,'

espoused by Edmund Husserl, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and George Herbert Mead,

among others, seeks to explain the mundane way in which social agents constitute

social reality through language, gesture, and all manner of symbolic social sign.

Though phenomenology sometimes appears to assume the existence of a choosing and constituting agent prior to language (who poses as the sole source of its con-

stituting acts), there is also a more radical use of the doctrine of constitution that

takes the social agent as an object rather than the subject of constitutive acts.

When Simone de Beauvoir claims, "one is not born, but, rather, becomes a woman,"

she is appropriating and reinterpreting this doctrine of constituting acts from the

phenomenological tradition.1 In this sense, gender is in no way a stable identity or

locus of agency from which various acts proceede; rather, it is an identity tenuously constituted in time-an identity instituted through a stylized repetition of acts. Further,

gender is instituted through the stylization of the body and, hence, must be under-

stood as the mundane way in which bodily gestures, movements, and enactments

of various kinds constitute the illusion of an abiding gendered self. This formulation

Judith Butler is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at George Washington University. She is the

author of Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflection in Twentieth-Century France. She has

published articles in post-structuralist and gender theory.

'For a further discussion of Beauvoir's feminist contribution to phenomenological theory, see my "Variations on Sex and Gender: Beauvoir's The Second Sex," Yale French Studies 172 (1986).

519

520 / Judith Butler

moves the conception of gender off the ground of a substantial model of identity to

one that requires a conception of a constituted social temporality. Significantly, if gender is instituted through acts which are internally discontinuous, then the appearance of substance is precisely that, a constructed identity, a performative accomplishment which the mundane social audience, including the actors themselves, come to believe

and to perform in the mode of belief. If the ground of gender identity is the stylized

repetition of acts through time, and not a seemingly seamless identity, then the

possibilities of gender transformation are to be found in the arbitrary relation between

such acts, in the possibility of a different sort of repeating, in the breaking or sub-

versive repetition of that style.

Through the conception of gender acts sketched above, I will try to show some

ways in which reified and naturalized conceptions of gender might be understood

as constituted and, hence, capable of being constituted differently. In opposition to

theatrical or phenomenological models which take the gendered self to be prior to

its acts, I will understand constituting acts not only as constituting the identity of

the actor, but as constituting that identity as a compelling illusion, an object of belief.

In the course of making my argument, I will draw from theatrical, anthropological,

and philosophical discourses, but mainly phenomenology, to show that what is called

gender identity is a performative accomplishment compelled by social sanction and

taboo. In its very character as performative resides the possibility of contesting its

reified status.

I. Sex/Gender: Feminist and Phenomenological Views

Feminist theory has often been critical of naturalistic explanations of sex and sex-

uality that assume that the meaning of women's social existence can be derived from

some fact of their physiology. In distinguishing sex from gender, feminist theorists

have disputed causal explanations that assume that sex dictates or necessitates certain

social meanings for women's experience. Phenomenological theories of human em-

bodiment have also been concerned to distinguish between the various physiological and biological causalities that structure bodily existence and the meanings that em-

bodied existence assumes in the context of lived experience. In Merleau-Ponty's

reflections in The Phenomenology of Perception on "the body in its sexual being," he

takes issue with such accounts of bodily experience and claims that the body is "an

historical idea" rather than "a natural species."2 Significantly, it is this claim that

Simone de Beauvoir cites in The Second Sex when she sets the stage for her claim that

"woman," and by extension, any gender, is an historical situation rather than a natural

fact.3

In both contexts, the existence and facticity of the material or natural dimensions

of the body are not denied, but reconceived as distinct from the process by which

the body comes to bear cultural meanings. For both Beauvoir and Merleau-Ponty,

2Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "The Body in its Sexual Being," in The Phenomenology of Perception, trans.

Colin Smith (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962). 3Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, trans. H. M. Parshley (New York: Vintage, 1974), 38.

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 521

the body is understood to be an active process of embodying certain cultural and

historical possibilities, a complicated process of appropriation which any phenom-

enological theory of embodiment needs to describe. In order to describe the gendered

body, a phenomenological theory of constitution requires an expansion of the con-

ventional view of acts to mean both that which constitutes meaning and that through which meaning is performed or enacted. In other words, the acts by which gender is constituted bear similarities to performative acts within theatrical contexts. My

task, then, is to examine in what ways gender is constructed through specific corporeal

acts, and what possibilities exist for the cultural transformation of gender through such acts.

Merleau-Ponty maintains not only that the body is an historical idea but a set of

possibilities to be continually realized. In claiming that the body is an historical idea,

Merleau-Ponty means that it gains its meaning through a concrete and historically mediated expression in the world. That the body is a set of possibilities signifies (a) that its appearance in the world, for perception, is not predetermined by some manner

of interior essence, and (b) that its concrete expression in the world must be un-

derstood as the taking up and rendering specific of a set of historical possibilities.

Hence, there is an agency which is understood as the process of rendering such

possibilities determinate. These possibilities are necessarily constrained by available

historical conventions. The body is not a self-identical or merely factic materiality; it

is a materiality that bears meaning, if nothing else, and the manner of this bearing is fundamentally dramatic. By dramatic I mean only that the body is not merely matter but a continual and incessant materializing of possibilities. One is not simply a body, but, in some very key sense, one does one's body and, indeed, one does

one's body differently from one's contemporaries and from one's embodied prede- cessors and successors as well.

It is, however, clearly unfortunate grammar to claim that there is a 'we' or an 'I'

that does its body, as if a disembodied agency preceded and directed an embodied

exterior. More appropriate, I suggest, would be a vocabulary that resists the substance

metaphysics of subject-verb formations and relies instead on an ontology of present

participles. The 'I' that is its body is, of necessity, a mode of embodying, and the

'what' that it embodies is possibilities. But here again the grammar of the formulation

misleads, for the possibilities that are embodied are not fundamentally exterior or

antecedent to the process of embodying itself. As an intentionally organized mate-

riality, the body is always an embodying of possibilities both conditioned and cir-

cumscribed by historical convention. In other words, the body is a historical situation, as Beauvoir has claimed, and is a manner of doing, dramatizing, and reproducing a

historical situation.

To do, to dramatize, to reproduce, these seem to be some of the elementary structures of embodiment. This doing of gender is not merely a way in which em-

bodied agents are exterior, surfaced, open to the perception of others. Embodiment

clearly manifests a set of strategies or what Sartre would perhaps have called a style of being or Foucault, "a stylistics of existence." This style is never fully self-styled, for living styles have a history, and that history conditions and limits possibilities. Consider gender, for instance, as a corporeal style, an 'act,' as it were, which is both

522 / Judith Butler

intentional and performative, where 'performative' itself carries the double-meaning of 'dramatic' and 'non-referential.'

When Beauvoir claims that 'woman' is a historical idea and not a natural fact, she

clearly underscores the distinction between sex, as biological facticity, and gender, as the cultural interpretation or signification of that facticity. To be female is, according to that distinction, a facticity which has no meaning, but to be a woman is to have

become a woman, to compel the body to conform to an historical idea of 'woman,' to

induce the body to become a cultural sign, to materialize oneself in obedience to an

historically delimited possibility, and to do this as a sustained and repeated corporeal

project. The notion of a 'project', however, suggests the originating force of a radical

will, and because gender is a project which has cultural survival as its end, the term

'strategy' better suggests the situation of duress under which gender performance

always and variously occurs. Hence, as a strategy of survival, gender is a performance with clearly punitive consequences. Discrete genders are part of what 'humanizes'

individuals within contemporary culture; indeed, those who fail to do their gender

right are regularly punished. Because there is neither an 'essence' that gender ex-

presses or externalizes nor an objective ideal to which gender aspires; because gender is not a fact, the various acts of gender creates the idea of gender, and without those

acts, there would be no gender at all. Gender is, thus, a construction that regularly

conceals its genesis. The tacit collective agreement to perform, produce, and sustain

discrete and polar genders as cultural fictions is obscured by the credibility of its

own production. The authors of gender become entranced by their own fictions

whereby the construction compels one's belief in its necessity and naturalness. The

historical possibilities materialized through various corporeal styles are nothing other

than those punitively regulated cultural fictions that are alternately embodied and

disguised under duress.

How useful is a phenomenological point of departure for a feminist description of

gender? On the surface it appears that phenomenology shares with feminist analysis

a commitment to grounding theory in lived experience, and in revealing the way in

which the world is produced through the constituting acts of subjective experience.

Clearly, not all feminist theory would privilege the point of view of the subject,

(Kristeva once objected to feminist theory as 'too existentialist')4 and yet the feminist

claim that the personal is political suggests, in part, that subjective experience is not

only structured by existing political arrangements, but effects and structures those

arrangements in turn. Feminist theory has sought to understand the way in which

systemic or pervasive political and cultural structures are enacted and reproduced

through individual acts and practices, and how the analysis of ostensibly personal situations is clarified through situating the issues in a broader and shared cultural

context. Indeed, the feminist impulse, and I am sure there is more than one, has

often emerged in the recognition that my pain or my silence or my anger or my

perception is finally not mine alone, and that it delimits me in a shared cultural

situation which in turn enables and empowers me in certain unanticipated ways.

The personal is thus implicitly political inasmuch as it is conditioned by shared social

4Julia Kristeva, Histoire d'amour (Paris: Editions Denoel, 1983), 242.

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 523

structures, but the personal has also been immunized against political challenge to

the extent that public/private distinctions endure. For feminist theory, then, the

personal becomes an expansive category, one which accommodates, if only implicitly,

political structures usually viewed as public. Indeed, the very meaning of the political

expands as well. At its best, feminist theory involves a dialectical expansion of both

of these categories. My situation does not cease to be mine just because it is the

situation of someone else, and my acts, individual as they are, nevertheless reproduce the situation of my gender, and do that in various ways. In other words, there is,

latent in the personal is political formulation of feminist theory, a supposition that

the life-world of gender relations is constituted, at least partially, through the concrete

and historically mediated acts of individuals. Considering that "the" body is invariably transformed into his body or her body, the body is only known through its gendered

appearance. It would seem imperative to consider the way in which this gendering of the body occurs. My suggestion is that the body becomes its gender through a

series of acts which are renewed, revised, and consolidated through time. From a

feminist point of view, one might try to reconceive the gendered body as the legacy of sedimented acts rather than a predetermined or foreclosed structure, essence or

fact, whether natural, cultural, or linguistic.

The feminist appropriation of the phenomenological theory of constitution might

employ the notion of an act in a richly ambiguous sense. If the personal is a category which expands to include the wider political and social structures, then the acts of

the gendered subject would be similarly expansive. Clearly, there are political acts

which are deliberate and instrumental actions of political organizing, resistance col-

lective intervention with the broad aim of instating a more just set of social and

political relations. There are thus acts which are done in the name of women, and

then there are acts in and of themselves, apart from any instrumental consequence, that challenge the category of women itself. Indeed, one ought to consider the futility of a political program which seeks radically to transform the social situation of women

without first determining whether the category of woman is socially constructed in

such a way that to be a woman is, by definition, to be in an oppressed situation. In

an understandable desire to forge bonds of solidarity, feminist discourse has often

relied upon the category of woman as a universal presupposition of cultural expe- rience which, in its universal status, provides a false ontological promise of eventual

political solidarity. In a culture in which the false universal of 'man' has for the most

part been presupposed as coextensive with humanness itself, feminist theory has

sought with success to bring female specificity into visibility and to rewrite the history of culture in terms which acknowledge the presence, the influence, and the op-

pression of women. Yet, in this effort to combat the invisibility of women as a category feminists run the risk of rendering visible a category which may or may not be

representative of the concrete lives of women. As feminists, we have been less eager, I think, to consider the status of the category itself and, indeed, to discern the

conditions of oppression which issue from an unexamined reproduction of gender identities which sustain discrete and binary categories of man and woman.

When Beauvoir claims that woman is an "historical situation," she emphasizes that

the body suffers a certain cultural construction, not only through conventions that

sanction and proscribe how one acts one's body, the 'act' or performance that one's

524 / Judith Butler

body is, but also in the tacit conventions that structure the way the body is culturally

perceived. Indeed, if gender is the cultural significance that the sexed body assumes,

and if that significance is codetermined through various acts and their cultural per-

ception, then it would appear that from within the terms of culture it is not possible to know sex as distinct from gender. The reproduction of the category of gender is

enacted on a large political scale, as when women first enter a profession or gain certain rights, or are reconceived in legal or political discourse in significantly new

ways. But the more mundane reproduction of gendered identity takes place through the various ways in which bodies are acted in relationship to the deeply entrenched

or sedimented expectations of gendered existence. Consider that there is a sedi-

mentation of gender norms that produces the peculiar phenomenon of a natural sex,

or a real woman, or any number of prevalent and compelling social fictions, and that

this is a sedimentation that over time has produced a set of corporeal styles which,

in reified form, appear as the natural configuration of bodies into sexes which exist

in a binary relation to one another.

II. Binary Genders and the Heterosexual Contract

To guarantee the reproduction of a given culture, various requirements, well-

established in the anthropological literature of kinship, have instated sexual repro- duction within the confines of a heterosexually-based system of marriage which

requires the reproduction of human beings in certain gendered modes which, in

effect, guarantee the eventual reproduction of that kinship system. As Foucault and

others have pointed out, the association of a natural sex with a discrete gender and

with an ostensibly natural 'attraction' to the opposing sex/gender is an unnatural

conjunction of cultural constructs in the service of reproductive interests.5 Feminist

cultural anthropology and kinship studies have shown how cultures are governed

by conventions that not only regulate and guarantee the production, exchange, and

consumption of material goods, but also reproduce the bonds of kinship itself, which

require taboos and a punitive regulation of reproduction to effect that end. Levi-

Strauss has shown how the incest taboo works to guarantee the channeling of sex-

uality into various modes of heterosexual marriage,6 Gayle Rubin has argued con-

vincingly that the incest taboo produces certain kinds of discrete gendered identities

and sexualities.7 My point is simply that one way in which this system of compulsory

heterosexuality is reproduced and concealed is through the cultivation of bodies into

discrete sexes with 'natural' appearances and 'natural' heterosexual dispositions.

Although the enthnocentric conceit suggests a progression beyond the mandatory structures of kinship relations as described by Levi-Strauss, I would suggest, along with Rubin, that contemporary gender identities are so many marks or "traces" of

5See Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (New York:

Random House, 1980), 154: "the notion of 'sex' made it possible to group together, in an artificial

unity, anatomical elements, biological functions, conducts, sensations, and pleasures, and it enabled

one to make use of this fictitious unity as a causal principle . . .". 6See Claude Levi-Strauss, The Elementary Structures of Kinship (Boston: Beacon Press, 1965). 7Gayle Rubin, "The Traffic in Women: Notes on the 'Political Economy' of Sex," in Toward an

Anthropology of Women, ed. Rayna R. Reiter (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1975), 178-85.

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 525

residual kinship. The contention that sex, gender, and heterosexuality are historical

products which have become conjoined and reified as natural over time has received

a good deal of critical attention not only from Michel Foucault, but Monique Wittig,

gay historians, and various cultural anthropologists and social psychologists in recent

years.8 These theories, however, still lack the critical resources for thinking radically

about the historical sedimentation of sexuality and sex-related constructs if they do

not delimit and describe the mundane manner in which these constructs are pro-

duced, reproduced, and maintained within the field of bodies.

Can phenomenology assist a feminist reconstruction of the sedimented character

of sex, gender, and sexuality at the level of the body? In the first place, the phe-

nomenological focus on the various acts by which cultural identity is constituted and

assumed provides a felicitous starting point for the feminist effort to understand the

mundane manner in which bodies get crafted into genders. The formulation of the

body as a mode of dramatizing or enacting possibilities offers a way to understand

how a cultural convention is embodied and enacted. But it seems difficult, if not

impossible, to imagine a way to conceptualize the scale and systemic character of

women's oppression from a theoretical position which takes constituting acts to be

its point of departure. Although individual acts do work to maintain and reproduce

systems of oppression, and, indeed, any theory of personal political responsibility

presupposes such a view, it doesn't follow that oppression is a sole consequence of

such acts. One might argue that without human beings whose various acts, largely

construed, produce and maintain oppressive conditions, those conditions would fall

away, but note that the relation between acts and conditions is neither unilateral nor

unmediated. There are social contexts and conventions within which certain acts not

only become possible but become conceivable as acts at all. The transformation of

social relations becomes a matter, then, of transforming hegemonic social conditions

rather than the individual acts that are spawned by those conditions. Indeed, one

runs the risk of addressing the merely indirect, if not epiphenomenal, reflection of

those conditions if one remains restricted to a politics of acts.

But the theatrical sense of an "act" forces a revision of the individualist assumptions

underlying the more restricted view of constituting acts within phenomenological discourse. As a given temporal duration within the entire performance, "acts" are a

shared experience and 'collective action.' Just as within feminist theory the very

category of the personal is expanded to include political structures, so is there a

theatrically-based and, indeed, less individually-oriented view of acts that goes some

of the way in defusing the criticism of act theory as 'too existentialist.' The act that

gender is, the act that embodied agents are inasmuch as they dramatically and actively

embody and, indeed, wear certain cultural significations, is clearly not one's act alone.

Surely, there are nuanced and individual ways of doing one's gender, but that one

does it, and that one does it in accord with certain sanctions and proscriptions, is

clearly not a fully individual matter. Here again, I don't mean to minimize the effect

8See my "Variations on Sex and Gender: Beauvoir, Wittig, and Foucault," in Feminism as Critique, ed. Seyla Benhabib and Drucila Cornell (London: Basil Blackwell, 1987 [distributed by University of Minnesota Press]).

526 / Judith Butler

of certain gender norms which originate within the family and are enforced through certain familial modes of punishment and reward and which, as a consequence,

might be construed as highly individual, for even there family relations recapitulate,

individualize, and specify pre-existing cultural relations; they are rarely, if ever,

radically original. The act that one does, the act that one performs, is, in a sense,

an act that has been going on before one arrived on the scene. Hence, gender is an

act which has been rehearsed, much as a script survives the particular actors who

make use of it, but which requires individual actors in order to be actualized and

reproduced as reality once again. The complex components that go into an act must

be distinguished in order to understand the kind of acting in concert and acting in

accord which acting one's gender invariably is.

In what senses, then, is gender an act? As anthropologist Victor Turner suggests in his studies of ritual social drama, social action requires a performance which is

repeated. This repetition is at once a reenactment and reexperiencing of a set of

meanings already socially established; it is the mundane and ritualized form of their

legitimation.9 When this conception of social performance is applied to gender, it is

clear that although there are individual bodies that enact these significations by

becoming stylized into gendered modes, this "action" is immediately public as well.

There are temporal and collective dimensions to these actions, and their public nature

is not inconsequential; indeed, the performance is effected with the strategic aim of

maintaining gender within its binary frame. Understood in pedagogical terms, the

performance renders social laws explicit.

As a public action and performative act, gender is not a radical choice or project that reflects a merely individual choice, but neither is it imposed or inscribed upon the individual, as some post-structuralist displacements of the subject would contend.

The body is not passively scripted with cultural codes, as if it were a lifeless recipient of wholly pre-given cultural relations. But neither do embodied selves pre-exist the

cultural conventions which essentially signify bodies. Actors are always already on

the stage, within the terms of the performance. Just as a script may be enacted in

various ways, and just as the play requires both text and interpretation, so the

gendered body acts its part in a culturally restricted corporeal space and enacts

interpretations within the confines of already existing directives.

9See Victor Turner, Dramas, Fields, and Metaphors (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1974). Clifford

Geertz suggests in "Blurred Genres: The Refiguration of Thought," in Local Knowledge, Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (New York: Basic Books, 1983), that the theatrical metaphor is used by recent social theory in two, often opposing, ways. Ritual theorists like Victor Turner focus on a notion of social drama of various kinds as a means for settling internal conflicts within a culture and regenerating social cohesion. On the other hand, symbolic action approaches, influenced by

figures as diverse as Emile Durkheim, Kenneth Burke, and Michel Foucault, focus on the way in

which political authority and questions of legitimation are thematized and settled within the terms of performed meaning. Geertz himself suggests that the tension might be viewed dialectically; his

study of political organization in Bali as a "theatre-state" is a case in point. In terms of an explicitly feminist account of gender as performative, it seems clear to me that an account of gender as ritualized,

public performance must be combined with an analysis of the political sanctions and taboos under which that performance may and may not occur within the public sphere free of punitive conse-

quence.

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 527

Although the links between a theatrical and a social role are complex and the

distinctions not easily drawn (Bruce Wilshire points out the limits of the comparison in Role-Playing and Identity: The Limits of Theatre as Metaphor'?), it seems clear that,

although theatrical performances can meet with political censorship and scathing

criticism, gender performances in non-theatrical contexts are governed by more clearly

punitive and regulatory social conventions. Indeed, the sight of a transvestite onstage can compel pleasure and applause while the sight of the same transvestite on the

seat next to us on the bus can compel fear, rage, even violence. The conventions

which mediate proximity and identification in these two instances are clearly quite different. I want to make two different kinds of claims regarding this tentative dis-

tinction. In the theatre, one can say, 'this is just an act,' and de-realize the act, make

acting into something quite distinct from what is real. Because of this distinction,

one can maintain one's sense of reality in the face of this temporary challenge to our

existing ontological assumptions about gender arrangements; the various conventions

which announce that 'this is only a play' allows strict lines to be drawn between the

performance and life. On the street or in the bus, the act becomes dangerous, if it

does, precisely because there are no theatrical conventions to delimit the purely

imaginary character of the act, indeed, on the street or in the bus, there is no

presumption that the act is distinct from a reality; the disquieting effect of the act is

that there are no conventions that facilitate making this separation. Clearly, there is

theatre which attempts to contest or, indeed, break down those conventions that

demarcate the imaginary from the real (Richard Schechner brings this out quite clearly in Between Theatre and Anthropology"). Yet in those cases one confronts the same

phenomenon, namely, that the act is not contrasted with the real, but constitutes a

reality that is in some sense new, a modality of gender that cannot readily be assim-

ilated into the pre-existing categories that regulate gender reality. From the point of

view of those established categories, one may want to claim, but oh, this is really a

girl or a woman, or this is really a boy or a man, and further that the appearance contradicts the reality of the gender, that the discrete and familiar reality must be

there, nascent, temporarily unrealized, perhaps realized at other times or other places. The transvestite, however, can do more than simply express the distinction between

sex and gender, but challenges, at least implicitly, the distinction between appearance and reality that structures a good deal of popular thinking about gender identity. If

the 'reality' of gender is constituted by the performance itself, then there is no recourse

to an essential and unrealized 'sex' or 'gender' which gender performances ostensibly

express. Indeed, the transvestite's gender is as fully real as anyone whose perform- ance complies with social expectations.

Gender reality is performative which means, quite simply, that it is real only to

the extent that it is performed. It seems fair to say that certain kinds of acts are

usually interpreted as expressive of a gender core or identity, and that these acts

either conform to an expected gender identity or contest that expectation in some

"Bruce Wilshire, Role-Playing and Identity: The Lmits of Theatre as Metaphor (Boston: Routledge and

Kegan Paul, 1981). "Richard Schechner, Between Theatre and Anthropology (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1985). See especially, "News, Sex, and Performance," 295-324.

528 / Judith Butler

way. That expectation, in turn, is based upon the perception of sex, where sex is

understood to be the discrete and factic datum of primary sexual characteristics. This

implicit and popular theory of acts and gestures as expressive of gender suggests that

gender itself is something prior to the various acts, postures, and gestures by which

it is dramatized and known; indeed, gender appears to the popular imagination as

a substantial core which might well be understood as the spiritual or psychological correlate of biological sex.12 If gender attributes, however, are not expressive but

performative, then these attributes effectively constitute the identity they are said to

express or reveal. The distinction between expression and performativeness is quite

crucial, for if gender attributes and acts, the various ways in which a body shows

or produces its cultural signification, are performative, then there is no preexisting

identity by which an act or attribute might be measured; there would be no true or

false, real or distorted acts of gender, and the postulation of a true gender identity

would be revealed as a regulatory fiction. That gender reality is created through sustained social performances means that the very notions of an essential sex, a true

or abiding masculinity or femininity, are also constituted as part of the strategy by

which the performative aspect of gender is concealed.

As a consequence, gender cannot be understood as a role which either expresses or disguises an interior 'self,' whether that 'self' is conceived as sexed or not. As

performance which is performative, gender is an 'act,' broadly construed, which

constructs the social fiction of its own psychological interiority. As opposed to a view

such as Erving Goffman's which posits a self which assumes and exchanges various

'roles' within the complex social expectations of the 'game' of modern life,13 I am

suggesting that this self is not only irretrievably 'outside,' constituted in social dis-

course, but that the ascription of interiority is itself a publically regulated and sanc-

tioned form of essence fabrication. Genders, then, can be neither true nor false,

neither real nor apparent. And yet, one is compelled to live in a world in which

genders constitute univocal signifiers, in which gender is stabilized, polarized, ren-

dered discrete and intractable. In effect, gender is made to comply with a model of

truth and falsity which not only contradicts its own performative fluidity, but serves

a social policy of gender regulation and control. Performing one's gender wrong

initiates a set of punishments both obvious and indirect, and performing it well

provides the reassurance that there is an essentialism of gender identity after all.

That this reassurance is so easily displaced by anxiety, that culture so readily punishes

or marginalizes those who fail to perform the illusion of gender essentialism should

be sign enough that on some level there is social knowledge that the truth or falsity

of gender is only socially compelled and in no sense ontologically necessitated.14

'2In Mother Camp (Prentice-Hall, 1974), Anthropologist Esther Newton gives an urben ethnography of drag queens in which she suggests that all gender might be understood on the model of drag. In Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), Suzanne J. Kessler and Wendy McKenna argue that gender is an "accomplishment" which requires the skills

of constructing the body into a socially legitimate artifice.

'3See Erving Goffmann, The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Garden City: Doubleday, 1959). 14See Michel Foucault's edition of Herculine Barbin: The Journals of a Nineteenth Century French

Hermaphrodite, trans. Richard McDougall (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), for an interesting display

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 529

III. Feminist Theory: Beyond an Expressive Model of Gender

This view of gender does not pose as a comprehensive theory about what gender is or the manner of its construction, and neither does it prescribe an explicit feminist

political program. Indeed, I can imagine this view of gender being used for a number

of discrepant political strategies. Some of my friends may fault me for this and insist

that any theory of gender constitution has political presuppositions and implications, and that it is impossible to separate a theory of gender from a political philosophy of feminism. In fact, I would agree, and argue that it is primarily political interests

which create the social phenomena of gender itself, and that without a radical critique of gender constitution feminist theory fails to take stock of the way in which op-

pression structures the ontological categories through which gender is conceived.

Gayatri Spivak has argued that feminists need to rely on an operational essentialism,

a false ontology of women as a universal in order to advance a feminist political

program. 5 She knows that the category of 'women' is not fully expressive, that the

multiplicity and discontinuity of the referent mocks and rebels against the univocity of the sign, but suggests it could be used for strategic purposes. Kristeva suggests

something similar, I think, when she prescribes that feminists use the category of

women as a political tool without attributing ontological integrity to the term, and

adds that, strictly speaking, women cannot be said to exist.16 Feminists might well

worry about the political implications of claiming that women do not exist, especially in light of the persuasive arguments advanced by Mary Anne Warren in her book,

Gendercide.17 She argues that social policies regarding population control and repro- ductive technology are designed to limit and, at times, eradicate the existence of

women altogether. In light of such a claim, what good does it do to quarrel about

the metaphysical status of the term, and perhaps, for clearly political reasons, fem-

inists ought to silence the quarrel altogether.

But it is one thing to use the term and know its ontological insufficiency and quite another to articulate a normative vision for feminist theory which celebrates or eman-

cipates an essence, a nature, or a shared cultural reality which cannot be found. The

option I am defending is not to redescribe the world from the point of view of women.

I don't know what that point of view is, but whatever it is, it is not singular, and

not mine to espouse. It would only be half-right to claim that I am interested in how

the phenomenon of a men's or women's point of view gets constituted, for while I

do think that those points of views are, indeed, socially constituted, and that a

reflexive genealogy of those points of view is important to do, it is not primarily the

gender episteme that I am interested in exposing, deconstructing, or reconstructing.

of the horror evoked by intersexed bodies. Foucault's introduction makes clear that the medical delimitation of univocal sex is yet another wayward application of the discourse on truth-as-identity. See also the work of Robert Edgerton in American Anthropologist on the cross-cultural variations of

response to hermaphroditic bodies. "Remarks at the Center for Humanities, Wesleyan University, Spring, 1985.

"6Julia Kristeva, "Woman Can Never Be Defined", trans. Marilyn A. August, in New French Fem- inisms, ed. Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron (New York: Schocken, 1981). 17Mary Anne Warren, Gendercide: The Implications of Sex Selection (New Jersey: Rowman and Al- lanheld, 1985).

530 / Judith Butler

Indeed, it is the presupposition of the category of woman itself that requires a critical

genealogy of the complex institutional and discursive means by which it is constituted.

Although some feminist literary critics suggest that the presupposition of sexual

difference is necessary for all discourse, that position reifies sexual difference as the

founding moment of culture and precludes an analysis not only of how sexual

difference is constituted to begin with but how it is continuously constituted, both

by the masculine tradition that preempts the universal point of view, and by those

feminist positions that construct the univocal category of 'women' in the name of

expressing or, indeed, liberating a subjected class. As Foucault claimed about those

humanist efforts to liberate the criminalized subject, the subject that is freed is even

more deeply shackled than originally thought.18

Clearly, though, I envision the critical genealogy of gender to rely on a phenom-

enological set of presuppositions, most important among them the expanded con-

ception of an "act" which is both socially shared and historically constituted, and

which is performative in the sense I previously described. But a critical genealogy needs to be supplemented by a politics of performative gender acts, one which both

redescribes existing gender identities and offers a prescriptive view about the kind

of gender reality there ought to be. The redescription needs to expose the reifications

that tacitly serve as substantial gender cores or identities, and to elucidate both the

act and the strategy of disavowal which at once constitute and conceal gender as we

live it. The prescription is invariably more difficult, if only because we need to think

a world in which acts, gestures, the visual body, the clothed body, the various physical

attributes usually associated with gender, express nothing. In a sense, the prescription

is not utopian, but consists in an imperative to acknowledge the existing complexity

of gender which our vocabulary invariably disguises and to bring that complexity

into a dramatic cultural interplay without punitive consequences.

Certainly, it remains politically important to represent women, but to do that in

a way that does not distort and reify the very collectivity the theory is supposed to

emancipate. Feminist theory which presupposes sexual difference as the necessary

and invariant theoretical point of departure clearly improves upon those humanist

discourses which conflate the universal with the masculine and appropriate all of

culture as masculine property. Clearly, it is necessary to reread the texts of western

philosophy from the various points of view that have been excluded, not only to

reveal the particular perspective and set of interests informing those ostensibly trans-

parent descriptions of the real, but to offer alternative descriptions and prescriptions;

indeed, to establish philosophy as a cultural practice, and to criticize its tenets from

marginalized cultural locations. I have no quarrel with this procedure, and have

clearly benefited from those analyses. My only concern is that sexual difference not

become a reification which unwittingly preserves a binary restriction on gender

identity and an implicitly heterosexual framework for the description of gender,

gender identity, and sexuality. There is, in my view, nothing about femaleness that

is waiting to be expressed; there is, on the other hand, a good deal about the diverse

'"Ibid.; Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage Books, 1978).

PERFORMANCE ACTS AND GENDER CONSTITUTION / 531

experiences of women that is being expressed and still needs to be expressed, but

caution is needed with respect to that theoretical language, for it does not simply

report a pre-linguistic experience, but constructs that experience as well as the limits

of its analysis. Regardless of the pervasive character of patriarchy and the prevalence of sexual difference as an operative cultural distinction, there is nothing about a

binary gender system that is given. As a corporeal field of cultural play, gender is

a basically innovative affair, although it is quite clear that there are strict punishments for contesting the script by performing out of turn or through unwarranted improvisa- tions. Gender is not passively scripted on the body, and neither is it determined by

nature, language, the symbolic, or the overwhelming history of patriarchy. Gender

is what is put on, invariably, under constraint, daily and incessantly, with anxiety and pleasure, but if this continuous act is mistaken for a natural or linguistic given,

power is relinquished to expand the cultural field bodily through subversive per- formances of various kinds.