Each response should be at least 150 words. State at least one interesting and what you consider intellectually challenging argument given about ethics and abortion from the course materials. Try to s

1 Reasonable Humans and Animals By John Simmons, Ph.D.

Philosophy Department, Addison College, NH “It is easy for us to criticize the prejudices of o ur grandfathers, from which our fathers freed themselv es. It is more difficult to distance ourselves from our own v iews, so that we can dispassionately search for prejudices a mong the beliefs and values we hold.” - Peter Singer "It's a matter of taking the side of the weak again st the strong, something the best people have always done." - Harriet Beecher Stowe In my 8 or so years experience of teaching philosop hy, ethics and logic courses, I have found that no topic bring s out the rational and emotional best and worst in people than ethical questions about the treatment of animals. This is n ot surprising since, unlike questions about social policy and abo ut what other people should do, moral questions about animals are personal . As philosopher Peter Singer has observed, “For most human beings, especially in modern urban and s uburban communities, the most direct form of contact with n on-human animals is at mealtimes: we eat them.” 1 For most of us, then, our own behavior is challenged when we reflect on t he reasons given to think that change is needed in our treatme nt of, and attitudes toward, animals. That the issue is person al presents unique challenges, and great opportunities, for int ellectual and moral progress.

Here I present some of the reasons given for and ag ainst taking animals seriously and reflect on the role of reason in our lives. I examine the common assumption that there is nothing wrong with harming animals -- causing them pain, suffering, and an early death – so they might be ea ten. We will see if moral “common sense” in this area can s urvive critical scrutiny. Our method, useful for better un derstanding all ethical debates, is to identify unambiguous and precise moral conclusions and make all the reasons in favor of the conclusion explicit, leaving no assumption unstated . Harms and Reasons Why is the treatment of animals a moral issue? Plut arch suggested an answer nearly two thousand years ago w hen he reflected on the killing of animals for food:

But for the sake of some little mouthful of flesh w e deprive a soul of the sun and light, and of that proportion of life and time it had been born into t he world to enjoy.

The simple answer is that animals are harmed by the practices required to bring them to our plates, and harms need rational defense. Chickens, pigs, cows, and other a nimals are conscious, can feel pleasure and pain, and their li ves can go better or worse, from their own point of view. Rais ing and killing them is bad for them: they experience pain, suffering, deprivation, boredom and an early death. Everything is taken 1 Peter Singer, Animal Liberation , 3 rd Ed. (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2002), p. 95. from them so that they might be eaten. And this is true regardless of the conditions they are raised in. Let us consider the common view that, even though it’s true that animals are harmed (indeed greatly harmed) by the practices required for meat eating, these practices are morally permissible nevertheless. We will see that common arguments for this perspective all have premises that are either false or in need of serious defense. The methods used in responding to these arguments will prove useful for addressing further arguments and objections beyond those discussed here. Defending Tradition One of the first things said is that it’s not wrong to harm animals for food because it’s a “tradition”: it’s s omething we do, and have done, for a long time. True, for many peop le, eating animals is a tradition. But not all traditions are good or ri ght: the important question is always whether an aspect of a tradition can be supported by good moral reasons or not. Also, fo r many people, eating animals is not a tradition: for thousands of years there have been people who extend their compassion to animals, and many other people who were raised eating animal s start new traditions when they see that consistency and moral reasoning demands change. Second, some people say that it’s “natural” to rais e and kill animals to eat them, so it’s right. But the meaning of “natural” is extremely obscure: people can mean very different t hings when they use the term. Whatever meaning one uses, howev er, it’s very hard to see how modern, industrial methods of facto ry farming, transport and slaughter are at all “natural.” It’s not even clear how an individual’s raising and killing, say, a pig or a chicken in her backyard would be “natural” either. But the relationship between what’s “natural,” in any sense of the term, and what’s morally right does not help th is argument.

Selfishness and cruelty are often quite “natural,” but they are not right or good. Walking on one’s hands is a quite “u nnatural” way to transport oneself, but it’s usually not wrong to do so. Some “natural” behaviors are right, but many are deeply wrong, and advocates of this argument forget that simple point . Whether something is “natural” or not is irrelevant to its morality. Third, some people insist that it’s nutritionally necessary to eat meat, milk and eggs and, therefore, it’s right that animals are raised and killed to be eaten. But this argument ig nores common sense and disrespects medical science. If it were t rue that we have to eat meat and other animal products, then there w ould be no people who abstain from doing do so because they wo uld all be dead. But there are such people, alive and well, an d medical science supplements common observations with eviden ce to show that they are often healthier than omnivores. 2 Consider the position statement of the leading authority on nutr ition in North America based on their seventeen-page review of the recent nutrition research:

It is the position of the American Dietetic Associa tion and Dietitians of Canada that appropriately planned veg etarian diets are healthful, nutritionally adequate, and pr ovide health benefits in the prevention and treatment of certain diseases. .

. Well-planned vegan and other types of vegetarian diets are appropriate for all stages of the life cycle, inclu ding during 2 pregnancy, lactation, infancy, childhood, and adolescence.

. . A vegetarian, including vegan, diet can meet cu rrent recommendations for all of these nutrients. . . Veg etarian diets offer a number of nutritional benefits, inclu ding lower levels of saturated fat, cholesterol, and ani mal protein as well as higher levels of carbohydrates, fiber, magnesium, potassium, folate, and antioxidants such as vitamins C and E and phytochemicals. Vegetarians ha ve been reported to have lower body mass indices than nonvegetarians, as well as lower rates of death fro m ischemic heart disease; vegetarians also show lower blood cholesterol levels; lower blood pressure; and lower rates of hypertension, type 2 diabetes, and prostate and colon cancer. 3 So this defense of eating animals is either ignoran t of, or disrespectful towards, the huge (and growing) body of research that shows the health benefits from eating a diet based on vegetables, legumes, fruits and whole grai ns, and ignores the growing literature detailing the variet y of harms for humans that can result from the production and consumption of animal products. 4 This argument thus has a false empirical premise: it is not supported by sci ence and medical research. A pattern is emerging, and we can use it to make a point about how to critically respond to reasoning given in ethics.

There are two useful critical ways to respond to mo ral arguments: an “Oh yeah?” response, and a “So what?” response. The former “Oh yeah?” response denies the truth of the premise and the latter “So what?” response deni es the truth of the (often unstated) assumption needed to validl y reach the conclusion. We can see these helpful responses in a ction by considering more arguments in favor of harming anim als. A fourth argument is based in the claim that “meat tastes good” or that it is pleasurable to eat it. But so what? Just because something causes pleasure doesn’t make it r ight. We do not think that pleasures automatically justify harming humans: if things are different in the animal case, we need reasons to see why this would be so. And, besides, there are many other pleasure-producing cuisines (often they are ethnic) to choose from that aren’t based on animal products anyway. A fifth argument is based on someone’s claiming tha t he or she “just couldn’t give up meat or dairy product s or eggs.” Oh yeah? Since so many other people have given these up, or never ate them in the first place, this claim is li kely disingenuous. And since this person probably hasn’t even tried changing his or her diet for moral reasons, he or s he likely lacks the evidence needed to confidently make that judgment. Sixth, people claim that animals eat other animals, so it’s right for us to do. Oh yeah? Only some animals eat other animals, and these are not chickens, pigs or cows. And so 3 “Position of the American Dietetic Association and Dietitians of Canada: Vegetarian Diets,” Journal of the American Dietetic Association, 2003;103:748-765. At http://www.eatright.org/cps/rde/xchg/ada/hs.xsl/adv ocacy_933_ENU _HTML.htm . 4 Eric Schlosser’s book and film Fast Food Nation vividly portrays the harms done to (immigrant) workers in slaughterh ouses, as does Gail Eisnitz’s Slaughterhouse: The Shocking Story of Greed, Neglec t, and Inhumane Treatment Inside the U.S. Meat Industr y. what?

Many animals do lots of things that we wouldn’t wa nt to do, and should not do (e.g., eat their own excremen t and, sometimes, their young), so why should we imitate a nimals in only some ways, but not others? A principled response is needed for this argument to have any force. Sometimes people say that we are animals, thinking that this justifies our killing and eating animals. But it do es not: just because we are animals does not mean that it’s morally right for us to do all the other things that other animals do; above we s aw many things that (some) animals do that would be wr ong for us to do. And if we are animals, we are unique animals wi th the ability to reason about the morality of our actions, in lig ht of their consequences for others. Should not we use this rea son to do what reduces harms to animals and ourselves? Seventh, people say eating meat is “convenient.” Oh yeah?

Many meat-based dishes are inconvenient to prepare, and plant- based dishes are usually as convenient as eating meat anyway. It’s just a matter of choosing something else from the s ame menu or same grocery store. But since doing the right thing sometimes requires our being inconvenienced in minor (and som etimes major) ways, so what? Eighth, it is sometimes said that we have a right to treat animals these ways, and that animals have no rights to not be treated these ways. That might be true, but reasona ble people want reasons for why they should think that. First, they will w ant to know what “right” is under consideration. Suppos e it’s the right to not be caused to suffer and die for someone else ’s pleasure. Is it because animals don’t do math problems, write no vels or make moral decisions that they don’t have this right? If so, since babies and many other humans don’t (and, for some, can’t) do these things, this view about moral rights denies them ri ghts also. Is it because animals are not biologically human that they lack the right to not be harmed for others? Interes tingly, nearly all philosophers who have considered these issues rejec t this kind of theory: on their views, the fact that we are biolog ically human has little to do with what we are owed, morally. This h ypothesis is confirmed, in part, by each of us asking us what it is about ourselves that, e.g., makes it such that it would be wrong to cause us pain and kill us. For most people, the obvious e xplanation is that this would hurt greatly, we would suffer enorm ously and our early deaths would prevent us from experiencing all the good things we (hopefully) would have experienced. It’s not because of some genes we have or where we are on some chart in a biology book that explains our moral status; rather, it is a matter of our vulnerability to physical and/or psychological harm . But since many animals are also vulnerable to such harms, these animals seem to be due the respect due to, at least, comparably-minded humans. Since this respect requires not raising and killing these humans for the mere pleasures of eating them, rational consistency requires the same treatm ent for chickens, cows, pigs and other animals who often ha ve far richer mental lives than many humans. Farming Facts These are just a few of the more common arguments g iven in defense of raising and killing animals for food. Th e fact that they are all quite weak suggests that people’s resistanc e to change regarding these issues might be based on non-ration al influences, not critical thinking and unbiased inquiry. But the fact that a strong defense of the status quo is lacking does not give us yet enough positive reason to think that animals are tr eated wrongly. 3 To see these reasons, we must consider in brief detail how are animals are harmed so that they might be served on our plates. The treatment of animals in farms and slaughterhous es has been well documented by all major print and television media. 5 On both “factory” and the few remaining “family” farms, baby animals are castrated, branded, ear and tail- docked, and teeth are pulled, all without (costly) anesthesia.

“Veal” calves, the male by-products of the dairy in dustry, spend their entire life individually chain at the n eck and confined to narrow stalls too narrow for them to tu rn around in. “Broiler” chickens, due to selective breeding a nd growth- promoting drugs, are killed at forty five days. Suc h fast growth causes chickens to suffer from a number of c hronic health problems, including leg disorders and heart disease.

“Layer” hens live a year or more in cages the size of a filing drawer, seven or more per cage, after which they ro utinely are starved for two weeks (“force molted”) to encourage another laying cycle. Female hogs are housed for four or fi ve years in individual barred enclosures ("gestation stalls") b arely wider than their bodies, where they are forced to birth l itter after litter. Until the recent “Mad Cow” scare, beef and dairy cattle too weak to stand (“downers”) were dragged or pushe d to their slaughter.

6 Many people would describe the treatment of animals in slaughterhouses as simply brutal: the title of a 20 01 Washington Post entitled “The Die Piece by Piece: In Overtaxed Plants, Humane Treatment of Cattle is Oft en a Battle Lost,” is suggestive of standard operating p rocedures in American slaughterhouses; more recent stories revea l similar inhumane conditions. A 2004 New York Times story documented workers at a chicken slaughterhouse stom ping on chickens, kicking them, and violently slamming them against floors and walls. Those attentive to the news media see stories like this all too often. One hopes that this treatment is not routine, but t here are is good reason to be skeptical of claims that it is not. After all, there are no laws protecting farmed animals, since they are explicitly excluded from the Animal Welfare Act. Th e Act says that, “the term ‘animal’ ... excludes horses n ot used for research purposes and other farm animals, such as, but not limited to, livestock or poultry, used or intended for food.” Reasonable Ethics So should we think that the harmful treatment of an imals in farms and slaughterhouses is wrong and should no t be supported? This conclusion follows only when moral principles are conjoined with facts about animal agribusiness and, perhaps, the fact that we do not need to eat a nimal products to survive and thrive. Fortunately, complex moral thinking is not needed t o find plausible principles to apply to this case. The sim ple, but powerful, “common sense” principle that we should avoid inflicting and supporting needless harm is all that is needed, 5 For reviews of this media coverage, see, among man y other sources, Dawn Animal World News Watch ( www.DawnWatch.com ) and Vegan Outreach ’s E-newsletter ( www.veganoutreach.org/enewsletter ). 6 For documentation and further information, see the literature produced by Vegan Outreach ( www.VeganOutreach.org ) and Compassion Over Killing ( www.COK.net and www.TryVeg.com ). and is supported by a wide range of theoretical per spectives – secular and religious – in ethics (in fact, nearly all of them). These theories urge that we should promote goodness and l essen badness or evil, respect all beings who are conscious and sentient (not just those who are “rational”), treat others as we would like to be treated, and otherwise promoting caring, compassion ate, sympathetic, sensitive and fair attitudes and behav ior. All of these theories condemn the practices of contemporary anim al agribusiness. This is true of both secular and religious moral po ints of view. About Christianity, It is very doubtful that Jesus – who advocated compassion, love and mercy – would suppor t the needless killing of animals for pleasure. Christian theologians and philosophers have carefully engaged these issues an d have argued that theology, the Bible and critical thinking abou t God’s will likely supports such compassion. 7 For those who insist that God supports killing animals for the pleasure of eating them, we need to ask them, first, how they might know that and, s econd, what reasons God would have for advocating eating animals, espe cially since it is often nutritional harmful for humans. Perspectives that deny that we should avoid inflict ing needless harm typically degenerate into infantile “ might-makes- right” moral theories or they falsely imply that it ’s only because “rational agents” care about non-rational beings (h umans and animals) that it’s be wrong to harm these beings. T his latter thought is mistaken because it’s wrong to harm thes e beings because they can be harmed , not because harming them would upset us. Thus, it seems that reasonable humans (all of whom have to eat and can easily choose animal-free foods; they cannot claim they are “too busy” to refrain from eating animals or that there are “more important things” to do, so they therefore must eat animals) should broaden their serious moral concern to include conscious, sentient beings who are not human: reasonable peopl e should not eat animals, since this is what the best moral reas ons support. One final response to arguments for vegetarianism i s a response common to many arguments about issues that challenge how we live our lives: “People are going to believe whatever they want to believe, and people are going to do whatever they want to do.” It’s important to realize that this response i s lamentable: it’s an evasion of the issues, since it does not engage the arguments.

For this issue, it’s an attempt to avoid rational e ngagement with uncomfortable questions about the lives and deaths of, each years, tens of billions of conscious, feeling beings. Those who are committed to the value of reason in g uiding our beliefs, attitudes, and even our feelings shoul d discourage this response, and promote reasonableness in all things, not just a select few, personally-convenient, topics. They sho uld do this also because this response is false: people sometimes do change their beliefs and behaviors, and on the basis of good rea sons. This is true about many issues, and confronting ethical iss ues about animals can often help us better see this for, and in, ourselves. The ultimate measure of a man is not where he stand s in moments of comfort and convenience, but where he st ands at times of challenge and controversy.

- Martin Luther King Jr. 7 See The Christian Vegetarian Association at www.ChristianVeg.com for an overview of this discussion and literature.