reading analysis (graduate level)

Abstract Objective We argue that people often fail to perceive and process stimuli easily available to them. In other words, we challenge the tacit assumption that aware- ness is unbounded and provide evidence that humans regularly fail to see and use stimuli and information easily available to them. We call this phenomenon ‘‘bounded awareness’’ (Bazerman and Chugh in Frontiers of social psychology:

negotiations, Psychology Press: College Park2005).

FindingsWe begin by rst describing perceptual mental processes in which obvious information is missed—that is, simply not seen—by the visual perceiver.

Inattentional blindness and change blindness are examples. We then extend this phenomenon to decision making and forecasting, using evidence about focalism to illustrate how people over focus on some information and fail to use other easily available information. We next examine how these processes of bounded aware- ness may extend to other important domains and across levels of analysis, such as information-sharing in groups, decision making in negotiators, and in competitive bidding situations such as auctions.

ConclusionsBounded awareness is a phenomenon that encompasses a variety of psychological processes, all of which lead to the same error: a failure to see, seek, use, or share important and relevant information that is easily seen, sought, used, or shared. KeywordsBounded awarenessÆFocusingÆFocalismÆWinner’s curseÆ Bounded rationalityÆInattentional blindnessÆChange blindness D. Chugh (&) Stern School of Business, New York University, Tisch 7-20, 44 West 4th Street, New York, NY 10012, USA e-mail: [email protected] M. H. Bazerman Harvard University, Baker Library 453, Soldier’s Field Road, Boston, MA 02163, USA e-mail: [email protected] 123 Mind & Society (2007) 6:1–18 DOI 10.1007/s11299-006-0020-4 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you Dolly ChughÆMax H. Bazerman Received: 29 October 2004 / Accepted: 23 May 2005 / Published online: 19 January 2007 Fondazione Rosselli 2007 1 Introduction Economists and psychologists rely on widely divergent assumptions about human behavior in constructing their theories. Economists tend to assume that people are fully rational, while psychologists, particularly behavioral decision researchers, identify the systematic ways in which people depart from rationality. Yet, while the two disciplines have offered different predictions of how individuals react to external stimuli, behavioral decision researchers and economists have shared the implicit assumption that individuals will accu- rately perceive the stimuli available to them.

In this paper, we argue that people actually often fail to perceive and process stimuli easily available to them. In other words, we challenge the tacit assumption that awareness is unbounded and provide evidence that humans regularly fail to see and use stimuli and information easily available to them.

We call this phenomenon ‘‘bounded awareness’’ (Bazerman and Chugh2005).

Herbert Simon introduced bounded rationality as a ‘‘behavioral model (in which) human rationality is very limited, very much bounded by the situation and by human computational powers’’ (1983, p. 34). The concept of bound- edness leads us to the important distinction between descriptive and norma- tive views of human behavior. A normative view of behavior is grounded in the assumption that the operation of the human mind is not constrained. A descriptive view of behavior is grounded in the assumption that mental pro- cesses are constrained in ways that make normative operations impossible.

Traditional economic theory is based upon a normative view of human behavior, while much of the work of today’s behavioral and experimental economists re ects a descriptive approach. Within psychology, the goal of generating descriptive theories has been to accurately predict how individuals, groups, and organizations will behave.

Here, we argue that people have ‘‘bounded awareness’’ that prevents them from focusing on easily observable and relevant data. We de ne bounded awareness as the phenomenon in which individuals do not ‘‘see’’ accessible and perceivable information during the decision-making process, while ‘‘seeing’’ other equally accessible and perceivable information; as a result, useful information remains out of focus for the decision-maker.

A ‘‘focusing failure’’ results from a misalignment between the information needed for a good decision and the information included in awareness. Our less formal de nition of a focusing failure is captured in the familiar ‘‘How could I have missed that?’’ reaction to the realisation that important infor- mation that could have been easily seen was ignored. We are deliberate and normative in our labeling of these instances as failures, as they represent costly errors. Researchers are just beginning to understand the systematic effects caused by our bounded awareness but we can and will demonstrate the suboptimality that results when individuals systematically ignore important information. We will argue that the focusing failures that arise from bounded awareness are indeed quite costly.

2 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 As illustrated in Fig.1, we propose that awareness is ‘‘bounded’’ when individuals fail to see, seek, use, or share highly relevant, easily accessible, and readily perceivable information during the decision-making process. In early stages, decision-makers may fail to see or seek out key information. Later, decision-makers may fail to use the information that they have within their awareness because the relevance of this information remains outside of awareness. Finally, individuals may be aware of key information that they fail to contribute to a group’s shared awareness despite its relevance to a group decision.

We begin by rst describing perceptual mental processes in which obvious information is missed—that is, simply not seen—by the visual perceiver. In- attentional blindness and change blindness are examples of processes in which individuals do not see or use clearly visible information. We then extend this phenomenon to decision making and forecasting, using evidence about fo- calism to illustrate how people over focus on some information and fail to use other easily available information. We next examine how these processes of bounded awareness may extend to other important domains and across levels of analysis. We discuss the tendency for groups to show bounded awareness by focusing on shared information and ignoring unique or unshared information held by group members. We examine bounded awareness in negotiators, particularly the tendency for the rules of the game and the decisions of the other party to be ignored. In competitive bidding situations such as auctions, we look at how bidders tend to ignore the impact of uncertainty and the number of competing bidders on their decision, often succumbing to the winner’s curse.

The diversity in the evidence we present will make it evident that bounded awareness is not a one-dimensional concept with a singular underlying mechanism. Rather, we are proposing that a wide range of psychological processes, including those of perception, attention, and cognitive reasoning, are subject to the errors of bounded awareness. We recognise that robust literatures exist on many well-established and related concepts and we make no attempt to thoroughly review them here. Rather, we strive to tie those seemingly disparate examples together with the concept of bounded aware- ness. Bounded awareness is a phenomenon that encompasses a variety of Fig. 1Possible manifestations of bounded awareness Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 3 123 psychological processes, all of which lead to the same error: a failure to see, seek, use, or share important and relevant information that is easily seen, sought, used, or shared.

2 Inattentional blindness Neisser (1979) presented a videotape of two visually superimposed teams passing basketballs, one wearing light-colored shirts and the other wearing dark-colored shirts, and asked participants to count the number of passes made between the two teams. Because the players were superimposed on top of each other, the task was moderately dif cult. To score accurately, partici- pants had to pay close attention to the task. Yet only 21% of participants reported seeing a woman abruptly and clearly walking through the group of players carrying an open umbrella. A repeated viewing of the videotape, without the counting task, reveals that the woman is unambiguously visible in the middle of the screen for a signi cant part of the video.

We have used this video in the classroom, and nd that an even smaller percentage notices the woman. After the rst showing of the video, during which students count passes, we ask whether anyone saw anything notewor- thy. In a large class, it is common for just a few people to mention seeing a woman with an umbrella. Predictably, others scoff at the suggestion. Yet, when we show the video for the second time, everyone sees the woman, leading to signi cant laughter and disbelief. This information sits visible and available in the visual eld, yet escapes awareness when competing with a task requiring other attentional resources.

Simons and Chabris (1999) have replicated and extended Neisser’s work with a video in which a person in a gorilla costume walks through a bas- ketball game, thumping his chest, and is clearly and comically visible for more than 5 s. Simons provides a series of such demonstrations on a video that is available at http://www.viscog.com. Recently, Simons and Chabris were awarded the ‘‘Ig Nobel Prize’’, an honor given for scienti c achieve- ment ‘‘which rst make you laugh, and then make you think’’ (Abrahams 1999). Since Neisser (1979) rst observed this phenomenon, now called ‘‘inattentional blindness’’ (Simons and Levin2003), it has become an important area of study for cognitive and perceptual psychologists. Mack and Rock (1998) demonstrate the phenomenon using perceptual experi- ments in which participants miss some information while focusing on other information. The consequences of inattentional blindness extend to real, life-and-death activities. For example, an airplane pilot who is attending to his controls could overlook the presence of another airplane in his runway (Mack2003). Similarly, cell phones can divert drivers’ attention, making inattentional blindness a likely contributor to car accidents. Moore and Egeth (1997) connect inattentional blindness to neural regions in the brain, and Mack (2003) identi es many key independent variables that affect the probability of not seeing the obvious.

4 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 3 Change blindness Change blindness is a perceptual phenomenon related to inattentional blindness. Change detection researchers have demonstrated that people fail to notice changes in the information that is visually available to them (Simons 2000). Interestingly, people often cannot describe the change that has taken place, but do demonstrate traces of memory of what they saw before the change. For example, an experimenter holding a basketball stopped pedes- trians to ask for directions (Simons et al.2002). While the pedestrian was giving directions, a group of people (confederates in the experiment) walked between the experimenter and the pedestrian. During this interruption, the experimenter handed the basketball to one person in the group. After giving directions, the pedestrian was asked if he or she noticed any sort of change during the brief exchange with the experimenter. Most did not. However, when led to think about a basketball, the pedestrian did recall seeing it at the beginning of the exchange, and some even recalled speci c features of the ball. So, while the participants failed to explicitly notice that a change took place, they did hold accurate implicit memory representations of both the pre- and post-change image.

Another example of change blindness is demonstrated in a study by Angelone et al. (2003). Participants watched a videotaped interaction in which easily visible clothing or objects were altered as the camera cut to different angles. Many participants failed to notice the change. Yet it was clear that they had perceived the initial visual stimulus, as they accurately selected the pre-change information from a photographic lineup. Additional studies by Mitroff et al. (2002) found similar patterns.

The possible in uence of change blindness in decision making is seen in a study in which participants are asked to choose the more attractive of two faces displayed on a computer screen (Johansson et al.2004). As participants moved the cursor to indicate their choice, a ash on the screen distracted them, and the two pictures were reversed. Nonetheless, most subjects con- tinued to move the cursor in the same direction, and selected the picture they originally viewed as the more attractive. Importantly, they both failed to notice the switch and provided reasons, post-hoc, to support their unintended decision.

The information that is missed in these studies is visual, and the mental processes at work appear to be perceptual. We believe that further research should explore how these processes operate when the information is not necessarily visual and the processes are not necessary perceptual. We antici- pate those studies will nd that other types of changes also go unnoticed, leading to important errors in decision-making. Bounded awareness, we be- lieve, will extend from perceptual processes to decision-making processes.

For example, Cain et al. (2005) describe the slippery slope of auditors becoming unethical. Essentially, they argue that auditors may be blind to changes made in corporate accounting practices as long as the changes are made slowly—on a slippery slope. Imagine that an accountant is in charge of Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 5 123 the audit of a large corporation with a strong reputation. The auditor and client have an excellent relationship, and the auditor receives tens of millions of dollars in fees from the client each year. For 3 years, the accountant has viewed and approved the client’s high-quality, extremely ethical nancial statements. Suddenly, the corporation begins stretching, and even breaking, the law in certain areas. If the accountant were asked if she noticed these transgressions, would she sign a statement certifying that the nancial state- ments were acceptable according to government regulations? Cain et al. be- lieve that most would notice and would refuse to sign.

Now suppose that the auditor saw and approved of high-quality, highly ethical nancial statements for 1 year, after which the corporation begins stretching the law in a few areas, but does not appear to break the law. The third year, the rm stretches the ethicality of its returns a bit more. Some of the company’s accounting decisions may now violate federal accounting standards. By the fourth year, the corporation has begun to stretch the law in many areas and occasionally to break it. Auditors are much more likely to notice and refuse to sign the statements in the rst version than in the second version, even if the unethical behavior is the same in year four of both stories.

This type of change blindness illustrates the ‘‘slippery slope’’ theory of unethical behavior (Cain et al.2005), which predicts that individuals are more likely to engage in unethical behavior that occurs in small increments than in unethical behavior that occurs suddenly. Decision makers are less likely to notice small changes and to code them as unethical than they are to code a dramatic change as wrong (Tenbrunsel and Messick2004).

Similarly, Gino and Bazerman (2005) show that people are less likely to perceive change if it occurs slowly over time rather then abruptly. They argue that recent business scandals such as the fall of Enron and Worldcom illustrate theboiling frog syndrome. According to this folk tale, if you place a frog in a pot of water, and raise the temperature ever so slowly, the gradual warming will comfort the frog into a state of relaxation. Eventually, however, the frog will die due to his inability to sense the gradual increase in water temperature.

4 Focalism and the focusing illusion ‘‘Focalism’’ is the common tendency to focus too much on a particular event (the ‘‘focal event’’) and too little on other events that are likely to occur concurrently (Gilbert and Wilson2000; Wilson et al.2000). Thus, individuals overestimate the degree to which their future thoughts will be occupied by the focal event as well as the duration of their emotional response to the event.

For example, individuals overestimate the impact of positive events, such as the win of a preferred sports team or political candidate, on their overall happiness. And even more dramatically, individuals overestimate the impact of negative events, such as a major medical condition, on overall happiness.

This error of bounded awareness is a failure to use information that is 6 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 available and known to the decision-maker, but not incorporated into the conscious decision-making process.

Using similar logic, Schkade and Kahneman (1998) de ne the ‘‘focusing illusion’’ as the human tendency to make judgments based on attention to only a subset of available information, to overweight that information, and to underweight unattended information. College students in the Midwest and in Southern California evaluated their own life satisfaction and the perceived life satisfaction of others. While Californians and Midwesterners reported similar levels of life satisfaction, both groups predicted that Californians had greater life satisfaction than Midwesterners. The factor that led to this pattern was that salient difference between California and the Midwest, such as climate, heavily in uenced non-residents’ judgments of residents’ life satisfaction.

Schkade and Kahneman argued that when Californians imagined moving to the Midwest, and vice versa, weather became a salient factor, and all other life events affecting satisfaction were outside of awareness. But these factors played a much smaller role in determining the experienced life satisfaction of residents of either region.

Again, these examples of bounded awareness show how decision makers can overlook and fail to see easily available information when considering the implications of future possible events. This tendency also occurs when indi- viduals are considering the probabilities of possible future events. When the 1995 National Basketball Association tournament reached the ‘‘elite eight’’, Fox and Tversky (1998) recruited basketball fans as participants. The subjects were asked to evaluate one of the following: (1) the probability that each team (Chicago, Indiana, Orlando, New York, Los Angeles, Phoenix, San Antonio, and Houston) would win the championship, (2) the probability that the win- ning team would come from each of the four divisions [Central (Chicago and Indiana), Atlantic (Orlando and New York), Paci c (Los Angeles and Phoenix), and Midwestern (San Antonio and Houston)], or (3) the probability that the winning team would come from either the Eastern conference (comprising the Central and Atlantic divisions) or the Western conference (comprising the Paci c and Midwestern divisions). If the participants were well calibrated, the sum of the probabilities in all three conditions (for the eight teams, for the four divisions, and for the two conferences) should each have added up to 100%.

The combined probabilities for the 2 conferences summed to 102%, close to the calibrated norm. But the sum of the probabilities of the 4 divisions was 144%; even more striking, the sum of the probabilities of the 8 teams was 218%. Fox and Tversky predicted and explained the nding by observing that when participants focus on a particular team, they see data to support that team winning the tournament; meanwhile, they do not see or use data to support the possibility of another team winning the tournament. In a similar study, Tversky and Koehler (1994) asked medical doctors to assess the probabilities of 4 mutually exclusive prognoses for a patient and found that the summed probability of the four diagnoses far exceeded 100%.

Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 7 123 The implications of focalism are not limited to laboratory studies. The Challenger space shuttle tragedy, for example, can be better understood through the lens of focalism (see Vaughn1996for a deeper analysis of this disaster). On 28 January 1986, the Challenger was launched at the lowest temperature in its history, leading to a failure of the ‘‘O-rings’’ and an explosion that killed all seven astronauts aboard. Before the launch, the decision makers at NASA examined seven prior launches in which some sort of O-ring failure occurred. No clear pattern between O-rings and temperature emerged from this data, and the launch continued as scheduled.

Critically, the decision makers failed to consider 17 previous launches in which no O-ring failure occurred. A logistic regression of all 24 launches would have led to an unambiguous conclusion: the Challenger had more than a 99% chance of malfunction. The scientists at NASA however, well meaning, caused a tragedy by missing information easily visible and accessible to them.

More broadly, the bounded awareness often results when decision-makers and groups limit their analysis to the data at hand, rather than seeking out information most relevant to the question being considered.

5 Bounded awareness in groups In terms of decision-making, one advantage of groups is that they collectively can possess, and utilize, more information than any individual. This advantage occurs in situations where individuals have and exchange unique information that is not held by other members of the group. However, this comparative advantage of groups is limited by the amount of unique information sharing that occurs in the group. In fact, a number of studies (Stasser and Titus1985; Stasser1988; Stasser and Stewart1992; Gruenfeld et al.1996) show that groups tend to focus much more on shared information than on unique or unshared information, thus reducing the advantage of the group over the individual as a decision-making body. Group awareness occurs when unique information is distributed throughout the group, thus minimizing the amount of uniquely held information in the group.

For example, Stasser and Titus (1985) asked college students to choose between three candidates running for student council president. The data provided favored Candidate A, who was preferred by 67% of individuals and 83% of groups comprised of these fully informed individuals. An alternative version of the exercise simulated the nature of information in most real-world groups. Some of the information about the candidates was held by all group members and some of it was unique, including much of the positive infor- mation about Candidate A. Now only 23% of the individuals in the unshared condition chose Candidate A. However, when the individuals were placed in groups, where every piece of needed information was held by at least one member, a mere 18% of the groups chose Candidate A.

Surprisingly, groups miss easily visible and accessible information, dem- onstrating a bounded awareness similar to that of individuals. In fact, groups 8 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 discuss shared information more often than unshared information (Stasser and Titus1985), despite the fact that groups are often created for the very purpose of increasing the amount of information available for a decision. A paradox emerges; groups are created to share unique information, yet devote their attention to commonly held information.

6 Bounded awareness in negotiations Two types of information are critical for any effective negotiator: the decisions of others and the rules of the game. However, due to bounded awareness, these types of information are often not seen or used by negotiators, leading to critical errors. We will use three types of negotiation problems to illustrate the phenomenon: multi-party ultimatum games, the Monty Hall problem, and the Acquiring a Company problem.

6.1 Multi-party ultimatum games In an ultimatum game, Player 1 divides a known, xed sum of money any way he chooses by lling out a form stating, ‘‘I demand X’’. Player 2 either accepts the offer and receives her share of the money as allocated by Player 1 or rejects the offer and leaves both parties with nothing. Concerns for fairness often lead Player 1s to be more generous and Player 2s to demand more than economic models suggest.

In this section, we examine multiple-party ultimatum games (Messick et al.

1997). In one multi-party version, six participants are assigned to the roles of A, B, C, D, E, and F. Player A is given $60 to allocate to the six parties and told that the offers to B, C, D, E, and F must be equal and must be an integer.

B, C, D, E, and F each record the minimum amount that they would accept from A.

Two versions of the problem exist, and differ in their decision rules. In the ‘‘largest amount’’ version, if the amount that A offers to B-F is equal to or greater than the largest amount requested by B, C, D, E, or F, then A’s allocation is distributed; if it is not, then all parties receive 0. In the ‘‘smallest amount’’ version, if the amount that A offers to B-F is equal to or greater than the smallest amount requested by B, C, D, E, or F, then A’s allocation offer is distributed; if it is not, then all parties received 0. As with the two-party ultimatum game, players B-F often respond in a bimodal fashion. Many B-F players accept $1, since $1 is better than the $0 they would receive from turning the offer down. But another large group of players B-F demand $10—they want their ‘‘fair’’ share. Since individuals underestimate disjunctive events (those that can occur independently) and overestimate conjunctive events (those that must occur in conjunction with one another) (Tversky and Kahneman1974), player As tend to underestimate the ease of persuading at least one out of ve people to accept $1 and overestimate the likelihood of all ve individuals accepting anything less than $10.

Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 9 123 Messick et al. (1997) demonstrated that players who offered anything less than 10-10-10-10-10-10 in the ‘‘largest amount’’ version tended to get $0 themselves (because the probability of getting even 15-9-9-9-9-9 is trivial). In addition, players who offered anything more than $1 or $2 to the other players in the ‘‘smallest amount’’ version did so because that wanted to be ‘‘fair’’ or because they made a bad decision; the expected payoff by player A’s fell dramatically as they increased their offers to B-F.

Bounded awareness leads to a failure to distinguish between these two problems. Yet, despite the surface similarities in the problems, the differences in the rules of the game and the likely decisions of the other party are sharply distinct. The effective negotiator focuses on these differences and uses this information to determine the rational response.

6.2 The Monty Hall game In the 1960s, Monty Hall was the host of the American television game show ‘‘Let’s Make a Deal’’. On the show, Monty would ask contestants to pick one of three doors. He and the contestants knew that one of the doors led to the grand prize and that the other two doors led to ‘‘zonks’’, which were small prizes or gag gifts. After a contestant picked a door, Monty would often open one of the other two doors, reveal a zonk, and then offer the contestant the chance to trade their chosen door for the remaining unchosen and unopened door. Most contestants preferred to stick with their original door.

Years after ‘‘Let’s Make a Deal’’ went off the air, statisticians, economists, and journalists became intrigued with the analytical choice faced by the contestants (Selvin1975; Nalebuff1987; vos Savant1990a,1990b,1991). Their analysis argued that contestants erred by not switching to the remaining un- chosen door. In addition, they argued against the common belief that, with only two doors remaining following the opening of one door by the host, the odds of winning the grand prize are 50-50.

The researcher proposed the following logic. When a contestant rst chose a door, she had a 1/3 chance of winning the prize. Let’s assume that Monty always opened an unchosen door (the ‘‘Monty always opens’’ condition) and then offered the contestant the opportunity to switch. When Monty opened one door to reveal a zonk, as he always could do, the 1/3 probability did not change. In other words, the contestant still had a 1/3 chance of having picked the grand prize from the start, and a 2/3 chance that the grand prize was behind one of the other two, unchosen doors. After Monty opens one zonk door, the 2/3 chance was now carried by the unopened, unchosen door.

Switching doors is the winning strategy, as it increases the participant’s odds of winning the grand prize from 1/3 to 2/3.

The critical assumption in this analysis was, ‘‘Monty always opens an un- chosen door’’. A different assumption would be the ‘‘Mean Monty’’ condition, in which Monty knew where the grand prize was located and made decisions in order to minimise the contestant’s chances of winning. So, after the con- testant picked a door, ‘‘Mean Monty’’ could either choose to end the game or 10 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 open one door and offer a switch. Because Monty was actively trying to minimise the probability that the contestant would win the grand prize, the contestant should never have accepted an offer from Monty to switch. In fact, Monty’s choice to offer a switch should have served as a signal that the contestant had already picked the winning door. 1 Thus, the winning strategy in the ‘‘Monty always opens’’ condition is to always switch doors, while the winning strategy in the ‘‘Mean Monty’’ con- dition is to never switch doors. Seeing the importance of Monty’s decision rule, and his likely decisions, is the key to the winning strategy. But bounded awareness can prevent individuals from seeing this readily available infor- mation.

6.3 Acquiring a Company In the Acquiring a Company problem, an acquiring rm has the opportunity to buy out a target rm. The acquiring rm does not know the exact current value of the target, only that it falls between $0 and $100 per share, with all values equally likely. The target rm is expected to be worth 50% more under the acquirer’s management than under the current ownership. Thus, it appears to make sense for a transaction to take place. The target rm can accept or reject the acquiring rm’s offer.

Consider the logic that would lead to a rational response when considering whether to make an offer of $60 per share:

If I offer $60 per share, the target will accept the offer 60% of the time—whenever the rm is worth between $0 and $60 to the target. Since all values between $0 and $60 are equally likely, the rm will, on average, be worth $30 per share to the acquirer, for a loss of $15 per share ($45– $60). Thus, a $60 per share offer is unwise.

Similar reasoning applies to any positive offer, such that, on average, the acquirer obtains a company worth 25% less than the price it pays when its offer is accepted. If the target accepts the acquirer’s offer of $X, the company is currently worth anywhere from $0 and $X. As the problem is formulated, any value in that range is equally likely. Thus, the expected value of the offer equals $X/2. Because the company is worth 50% more to the acquirer, the expected value to the acquirer is 1.5($X/2) = 0.75($X), just 75% of its offer price. Thus, for any value of $X, the acquirer’s best option is to not make an offer ($0 per share). The paradox of the problem is that although the rm is always worth more to the acquirer than to the target, any offer higher than $0 generates a negative expected return to the acquirer. The paradox results from the high likelihood that the target will accept the acquirer’s offer when the rm is least valuable to the acquirer—in other words, when it is a ‘‘lemon’’ (Akerlof1970). 1In a dynamic game-theoretic equilibrium, the contestant would not know that she won, but should still keep her original choice.

Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 11 123 The Acquiring a Company problem demonstrates the ‘‘winner’s curse’’, where one side, typically the seller, often has much better information than the other side, putting the buyer at a disadvantage. A structural asymmetry is built into the problem: a rational buyer will bid $0 despite the fact that the buyer’s valuation of the company is higher than the seller’s valuation. The strategic seller will not provide the buyer with information about the com- pany’s true value, especially when that value is low. As a result, to avoid an expected value loss, game theory recommends that buyers not make any offer.

In all three of these seemingly very different negotiation problems (multi- party ultimatum games, the Monty Hall Game, and the Acquiring a Company problem), people tend to ignore the rules of the game and the decisions of the opposing party (Tor and Bazerman2003). The problems are not analytically dif cult and all of the information the negotiator needs is easily seen. Yet, in the multi-party ultimatum game, Player As allocated an average of $8.15 to the other players in the ‘‘smallest amount’’ condition), while allocating $8.47 to the other players in the ‘‘largest amount’’). These results re ect bounded awareness, as the optimal strategies for Player A should be dramatically dif- ferent between the two conditions (offers of $1 vs. $10). Players are passing up signi cant pro t due to this error.

In the ‘‘always open’’ condition of the Monty Hall problem, Friedman (1998) has found that most people do not switch doors, essentially opting for a 1/3 chance of winning rather than trading for a 2/3 chance. Tor and Bazerman (2003) found that 59% of participants behave in this suboptimal manner. But in the Mean Monty version, 79% made the right decision to keep the existing door. Finally, the majority of participants made the same decision in both versions of the game; only 24% answered both versions correctly. The key ‘‘Monty Hall’’ result in Tor and Bazerman (2003) is that the consistency across the two very different versions of the game demonstrate that the rules of the game and the decisions of others are outside the bounds of awareness for most decision-makers.

The game that most extensively demonstrates bounded awareness is ‘‘Acquiring a Company’’. Extensive research on this problem suggests that bounded awareness leads decision makers to ignore or simplify the cognitions of opposing parties as well as the rules of the game (Tor and Bazerman2003; Carroll et al.1988). Across studies, the modal response range falls between $50 and $75. The common reasoning is: ‘‘On average, the rm will be worth $50 to the target and $75 to the acquirer; consequently, a transaction in this range will, on average, be pro table to both parties’’. Typically, less that 10 percent of participants offer $0 per share. Replications with accounting rm partners, CEOs, investment bankers, and many other skilled groups have produced similar results. Finally, even participants who were paid according to their performance and given many opportunities to learn through experience exhibited the same pattern of responses (Ball et al.1991; Grosskopf and Bereby-Meyer2005).

Most people can follow the logic that the optimal offer in this problem is $0 per share, yet when unaided, most people make a positive offer. Why? Be- 12 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 cause they systematically exclude information from their decision-making processes that they have the ability to include. They overlook the fact that their expected return depends on an acceptance by the other party, which in turn is affected by the rules of the game, which state that the other side knows its true value before accepting or rejecting the offer. This logic implies that acceptance by the target is most likely to occur when the acquirer is in the least desirable position.

Respondents overwhelmingly have provided solutions that yield a negative expected return. But in a recent adaptation of the Acquiring a Company exercise, Valley et al. (1998) found that when parties talk face-to-face, they can make a trade at a mutually bene cial value. Thus, social interaction can overcome the inef cient outcomes predicted by game theory and behavioral decision theory. Valley et al. suggest that communication motivates parties to create bene ts for the other side, facilitates trust, and allows for the type of information exchange not predicted by game theoretic models. Essentially, the social context of face-to-face interaction helps negotiators overcome bounded awareness.

These three problems illustrate how the rules of the game and the decisions of others, two critical and often accessible pieces of information in a negoti- ation, can be out of focus to negotiators. We believe that these documented focusing failures help to explain negotiation failures beyond the three prob- lems presented here. Camerer and Lovallo (1999) use the expression ‘‘refer- ence group neglect’’ to describe the tendency of people to be insensitive to the quality of their competition. Along these lines, Moore and colleagues (Moore and Kim2003; Moore and Small2004) have found that people expect to perform better than average on easy problems, but worse than average on hard problems, ignoring the fact that easy or hard problems are easy or dif- cult for most people as well. Moore (2000) also has observed bounded awareness in the context of negotiation deadlines. In a negotiation in which both buyer and seller receive zero payoff if they fail to reach agreement, Moore imposes a publicly known deadline on one party, which intuitively appears to put that party at a disadvantage. Of course, both sides should recognise that if one party has a deadline, the other does too. Yet negotiators tend to believe that a deadline put them at an asymmetric disadvantage. In another experiment, Moore imposes time-related costs on one party, costs that do give an advantage to the party without time-related costs. Moore then gives the party with time-related costs the opportunity to impose a rm deadline on the negotiation, thereby eliminating the individual’s asymmetric time-related costs and creating symmetric costs for the failure to reach agreement. Most people reject this option, despite its strategic bene t. By failing to consider how the rules of the game affect the other party, individuals suboptimise their outcomes.

A related phenomenon is ‘‘system neglect’’ (Massey and Wu2005), or the human tendency to undervalue the importance of the general decision-making context. One notable example of this type of bounded awareness is the longtime failure of US citizens to treat campaign- nance reform as an Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 13 123 important means of curbing the undue in uence of special-interest groups on the political process (Bazerman et al.2001). When asked whether they sup- port the issue of campaign- nance reform, most people say ‘‘yes’’. Yet they tend to rank it very low in their list of priorities, relative to other issues.

Bazerman et al. (2001) argue that voters undervalue campaign- nance reform because of their bounded awareness of the critical indirect impact of campaign nance reform on other issues important to them. Failing to think through this process, people tend instead to value issues that are more clearly seen as end states or outcomes, such as tax cuts or education. A broader awareness would direct their attention toward a set of outcomes that would have a large, po- sitive effect on many issues (Bazerman et al.2001).

Finally, bounded awareness can prevent negotiators from considering the impact of their decisions on outsiders. Decision and negotiation scholars have promoted cooperation in prisoner dilemma games and social dilemmas. In a prisoner dilemma game, two or more parties would be jointly better off if they both cooperated rather than if they both defected (betrayed each other), yet each party would be better off defecting on the other, regardless of the behavior of the other party. The prisoner dilemma problem has been used to understand defection in the nuclear arms race, the failure of strategic alli- ances, and the overharvesting and over shing crises. In these realms and others, negotiators make gains at the expense of others outside of the bounds of the problem or crisis.

7 Bounded awareness in auctions Bounded awareness extends beyond individual perception and decision- making and into competitive situations. We return now to the ‘‘winner’s curse’’, which Bazerman and Samuelson (1983) describe as a situation such as a two-party negotiation between buyer and seller in which the buyer errs by ignoring the perspective of the seller. In auctions, the winner’s curse occurs when the winning bidder fails to consider that he or she has bid higher than everyone else, despite the fact that all bidders have an information disad- vantage relative to the seller. Bazerman and Samuelson (1983) argue that the highest bidder may have signi cantly overestimated the worth of the item they have just purchased.

Figure2illustrates this argument. Curve E depicts the distribution of bid- der estimates for the true value of the commodity. Curve B shows the dis- tribution of bids. The depiction assumes that (1) the mean of the distribution equals the true value of the commodity—that no aggregate under—or over- estimation is expected; and (2) bidders discount their estimates a xed amount when making bids, thus explaining the leftward shift of the estimate distri- bution. The gure suggests that a winning bid—one from the right tail of the distribution—will probably exceed the actual value of the commodity. The highest bidder is likely also to have been one of the highest estimators; unless they had reason to believe that they had better information than other bid- 14 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 ders, overpayment is likely. In fact, we have found in our research (Samuelson and Bazerman1985) that the winning bidder in auctions of highly uncertain commodities with a large number of bidders typically pays more than the commodity is worth.

If an individual bidder or group of bidders assumes that their bid will win the auction, this assumption should tell them that they may very well have overestimated the value of the commodity relative to other bidders. Based on this reasoning, bidders on highly uncertain commodities who are competing against a large number of bidders should lower their estimates of the true value of the commodity as well as their bids. Thus, if they do end up winning, they are less likely to have overbid, or at least not by a smaller margin. But most people ignore the effects of uncertainty, even falsely viewing the pres- ence of many bidders as a sign that they should be con dent of the com- modity’s value and quality.

We propose that bounded awareness is the psychological process that ex- plains the information left out of the decision-making process, leading to the winner’s curse. In the 1980s, Wall Street saw a blitz of acquisition activity, in which companies often competed destructively against each other to win a takeover battle and paid too much for what they ‘‘won’’. Not surprisingly, two- thirds of acquisitions turn out to be failures or fall short of expectations.

8 Conclusion Bounded awareness could viably be included under a broad de nition of bounded rationality, one of the most powerful concepts to emerge in the social sciences. But we believe that bounded awareness research emphasizes a Fig. 2Winner’s curse in auctions Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 15 123 direction quite different from recent operationalizations of bounded ratio- nality. In our view, most work that is positioned as part of modern-day bounded rationality focuses on imperfections in the integration of data in the decision-making process. As a result of this perspective, other aspects of decision perfection are missed.

In work parallel to our own, Thaler (2000) suggested that there are two additional ways in which decision making is limited, which he describes as ‘‘bounded willpower’’ and ‘‘bounded self-interest’’. The former describes the pervasive human tendency to give greater weight to present concerns than to future concerns, leading to inconsistencies between temporary motivations and long-term interests. The latter notes that our self-interest is bounded; unlike the stereotypic economic actor, we care about the outcomes of others.

Similarly, Chugh et al. (2005) have introduced the concept of ‘‘bounded ethicality’’ to refer to the limits on our ethics of which we are not even aware.

We now add the term bounded awareness. Together, these concepts provide a speci c roadmap of how human judgment departs from economic models and common intuition.

We are not advocating an unrealistic state of unboundedness, nor are we denying the potential adaptive bene ts of cognitive ef ciency. But, we pro- pose that people tend to overestimate their own awareness and underestimate the bounds on their awareness, demonstrating a stubborn resistance to the very existence of bounded awareness. Subsequently, they disbelieve that they have overlooked information crucial to making a successful decision. The failure to recognise these normal psychological limitations poses an even greater danger than the limitation itself. That is, the risks of the meta-error may exceed those of the error itself.

In fact, we suspect that people tend to over-search for information in lower priority contexts and under-search in higher priority contexts. The costs of bounded awareness are greatest, then, in the contexts where the decisions are of the highest priority. In lower priority situations, the adaptive bene ts of bounded awareness may, in fact, outweigh the costs.

Our goal in this article has been to specify the nature of the ways in which our awareness is bounded. We are sure that there are many other bounds to human awareness, and we look forward to developments of this understand- ing. But if we have convinced you that readily available and important information exists that you and others miss on a systematic and predictable basis, this article has served its purpose.

References Abrahams M (1999) What is this Ig? http://www.improbable.com/ig/what is this ig.html (October 1, 2004) Akerlof G (1970) The market for lemons. Q J Econ 89:488-500 Angelone BL, Levin DT, Simons DJ (2003) The relationship between change detection and recognition of centrally attended objects in motion pictures. Perception 32(8):947-962 16 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123 Ball SB, Bazerman MH, Carroll JS (1991) An evaluation of learning in the bilateral winner’s curse. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 48:1-22 Bazerman MH, Chugh D (2005) Bounded awareness: Focusing failures in negotiation. In:

Thompson L (eds) Frontiers of social psychology: negotiations. Psychology Press, College Park Bazerman MH, Samuelson WF (1983) I won the auction but don’t want the prize. J Con ict Resolut 27:618-634 Bazerman MH, Baron J, Shonk K (2001) You can’t enlarge the pie: six barriers to effective government. Basic Books, New York Cain DM, Loewenstein G, Moore DA (2005) The dirt on coming clean: perverse effects of disclosing con icts of interest. J Legal Stud 34(1):1-27 Camerer C, Lovallo D (1999) Overcon dence and excess entry: an experimental approach. Am Econ Rev 89(1):306-318 Carroll JS, Bazerman MH, Maury R (1988) Negotiator cognitions: a descriptive approach to negotiators’ understanding of their opponents. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 41(3):352- 370 Chugh D, Bazerman MH, Banaji MR (2005) Bounded ethicality as a psychological barrier to recognizing con icts of interest. In: Moore DA, Cain DM, Loewenstein G, Bazerman MH (eds) Con icts of interest: problems and solutions from law, medicine and organizational settings. Cambridge University Press, London, pp 74-95 Fox CR, Tversky A (1998) A belief-based account of decision under uncertainty. Manage Sci 44(7):879-895 Friedman D (1998) Monty Hall’s three doors: construction and deconstruction of a choice anomaly. Am Econ Rev 88(4):933-946 Gilbert DT, Wilson TD (2000) Miswanting: some problems in the forecasting of future affective states. In: Forgas JP (ed) Feeling and thinking: the role of affect in social cognition. Series:

Studies in emotion and social interaction. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 178-197 Gino F, Bazerman MH (2005) Slippery slopes and misconduct: the effect of gradual degradation on the failure to notice unethical behavior. Harvard Business School working paper 06-019 Grosskopf B, Bereby-Meyer Y (2005) Overcoming the winner’s curse: an adaptive learning per- spective. Working paper Gruenfeld D, Mannix EA, Williams KY, Neale MA (1996) Group composition and decision making: How member familiarity and information distribution affect process and perfor- mance. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 67:1-15 Johansson P, Hall L, Olsson A, Sikstrom S (2004) From change blindness to choice blindness. In:

Paper for the conference toward a science of consciousness conference, April 7-11, Tucson Mack A (2003) Inattentional blindness: looking without seeing. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 12(5):180-184 Mack A, Rock I (1998) Inattentional blindness. Series: Bradford books series in cognitive psy- chology. The MIT Press, Cambridge Massey C, Wu G (2005) Detecting regime shifts. Manage Sci 51(6):932-947 Messick DM, Moore DA, Bazerman MH (1997) Ultimatum bargaining with a group: underesti- mating the importance of the decision rule. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 69(2):87-101 Mitroff SR, Simons DJ, Franconeri SL (2002) The siren song of implicit change detection. J Exp Psychol Human Percept Perform 28:798-815 Moore DA (2000) The unexpected bene ts of negotiating under time pressure. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Northwestern University, Evanston Moore CM, Egeth H (1997) Perception without attention: Evidence of grouping under conditions of inattention. J Exp Psychol Human Percept Perform 23(2):339-352 Moore DA, Kim TG (2003) Myopic social prediction and the solo comparison effect. J Pers Soc Psychol 85(6):1121-1135 Moore DA, Small DA (2004) Error and bias in comparative social judgment: On being both better and worse than we think we are. Tepper working paper 2004-E1, Pittsburgh Moore DA, Cain DM, Loewenstein G, Bazerman MH (eds) (2005) Con icts of interest: Chal- lenges and solutions in business, law, medicine, and public policy. Cambridge University Press, New York Nalebuff B (1987) Puzzles: Choose a curtain, duel-ity, two point conversions, and more. J Econ Perspect 1(1):157-163 Neisser U (1979) The concept of intelligence. Intelligence 3(3):217-227 Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you 17 123 Samuelson WF, Bazerman MH (1985) Negotiating under the winner’s curse. In: Smith V (ed) Research in experimental economics, vol 3. JAI Press, Greenwich CT, pp 105-137 Schkade DA, Kahneman D (1998) Does living in California make people happy? A focusing illusion in judgments of life satisfaction. Psychol Sci 9(5):340-346 Selvin S (1975) Letter to the editor. Am Stat 29:67 Simon HA (1983) Reason in human affairs.Stanford University Press, Stanford CA Simons DJ (2000) Current approaches to change blindness. Visual Cogn 7(1-3):1-15 Simons DJ, Chabris CF (1999) Gorillas in our midst: Sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception 28(9):1059-1074 Simons DJ, Levin D (2003) What makes change blindness interesting? In: Irwin DE Ross BH (eds) The psychology of learning and motivation. Academic, San Diego Simons DJ, Chabris CF, Schnur T, Levin DT (2002) Evidence for preserved representations in change blindness. Conscious Cogn 11(1):78-97 Stasser G (1988) Computer simulation as a research tool: the DISCUSS model of group decision making. J Exp Soc Psychol 24:393-422 Stasser G, Stewart D (1992) Discovery of hidden pro les by decision-making groups: solving a problem versus making a judgment. J Pers Soc Psychol 63(3):426-434 Stasser G, Titus W (1985) Pooling of unshared information in group decision making: biased information sampling during discussion. J Pers Soc Psychol 48:1467-1478 Tenbrunsel AE, Messick DM (2004) Ethical fading: the role of self deception in unethical behavior. Soc Justice Res 17(2):223-236 Thaler R (2000) From Homo economicus to Homo sapiens. J Econ Perspect 14:133-141 Tor A, Bazerman MH (2003) Focusing failures in competitive environments: explaining decision errors in the Monty Hall game, the Acquiring a Company problem, and multi-party ultima- tums. J Behav Decis Making 16(5):353-374 Tversky A, Kahneman D (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185:1124-1130 Tversky A, Koehler DJ (1994) Support theory: a nonextensional representation of subjective probability. Psychol Rev 101:547-567 Valley KL, Moag JS, Bazerman MH (1998) A matter of trust: effects of communication on the ef ciency and distribution of outcomes. J Econ Behav Organ 34:211-238 Vaughn D (1996) The challenger launch decision: risky technology, culture, and deviance at NASA.University of Chicago, Chicago vos Savant M (1990a) Ask Marilyn. Parade Magazine, September 9 vos Savant M (1990b) Ask Marilyn. Parade Magazine. December 2 vos Savant M (1991) Ask Marilyn. Parade Magazine.February 17 Wilson TD, Wheatley T, Meyers JM, Gilbert DT, Axsom D (2000) Focalism: a source of dura- bility bias in affective forecasting.J Pers Soc Psychol 78(5):821-836 18 D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman 123